Hostname: page-component-8448b6f56d-c47g7 Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-04-23T07:57:19.661Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

EPISTEMIC INTUITIONS IN FAKE-BARN THOUGHT EXPERIMENTS

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  31 March 2014

Abstract

In epistemology, fake-barn thought experiments are often taken to be intuitively clear cases in which a justified true belief does not qualify as knowledge. We report a study designed to determine whether members of the general public share this intuition. The data suggest that while participants are less inclined to attribute knowledge in fake-barn cases than in unproblematic cases of knowledge, they nonetheless do attribute knowledge to protagonists in fake-barn cases. Moreover, the intuition that fake-barn cases do count as knowledge is negatively correlated with age; older participants are less likely than younger participants to attribute knowledge in fake-barn cases. We also found that increasing the number of defeaters (fakes) does not decrease the inclination to attribute knowledge.

Type
Articles
Copyright
Copyright © Cambridge University Press 2014 

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

References

REFERENCES

Alexander, J. and Weinberg, J. M. 2007. ‘Analytic Epistemology and Experimental Philosophy.Philosophy Compass, 2(1): 5680.Google Scholar
Beebe, J. and Sakris, D. 2011. ‘Moral Objectivism across the Life Span.’ Society for Empirical Ethics Meeting at the Pacific Division Meeting of the American Philosophical Association. San Diego, CA, 20 April 2011.Google Scholar
Beebe, J. R. and Undercoffer, R. J. MS. ‘Individual and Cross-Cultural Differences in Semantic Intuitions: New Experimental Findings.’Google Scholar
Bonsang, E. and Dohmen, T. 2012. ‘Cognitive Ageing and Risk Attitude.’ SSRN. http://papers.ssrn.com/sol3/papers.cfm?abstract_id=2013220.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Buckwalter, W. MS. ‘Factive Verbs and Protagonist Projection.’ City University of New York, Graduate Center.Google Scholar
Buckwalter, W.. 2012. ‘Non-traditional Factors in Judgments about Knowledge.Philosophy Compass, 7(4): 278–89.Google Scholar
Buckwalter, W. and Schaffer, J. Forthcoming. ‘Knowledge, Stakes and Mistakes’. Nous.Google Scholar
Buckwalter, W. and Stich, S. 2011. ‘Epistemology and Demography.’ Invited presentation at the Pre-Conference Workshop in Experimental Epistemology. American Philosophical Association Pacific Meeting, 20 April 2011.Google Scholar
Buckwalter, W. and Stich, S.. 2013. ‘Gender and Philosophical Intuition.’ In Knobe, J. and Nichols, S. (eds), Experimental Philosophy, Vol. 2, pp. 307346. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Cohen, J. 1992. ‘A Power Primer.Psychological Bulletin, 112(1): 155–9.Google Scholar
Cullen, S. 2010. ‘Survey-driven Romanticism.Review of Philosophy and Psychology, 1: 275–96.Google Scholar
De Rose, K. 2009. The Case for Contextualism: Knowledge, Skepticism, and Context, Vol. 1. New York: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Dunaway, B., Edmonds, A. and Manley, D. 2013. ‘The Folk Probably do Think What you Think they Think.Australasian Journal of Philosophy, 91: 421–41.Google Scholar
Fantl, J. and McGrath, M. 2002. ‘Evidence, Pragmatics and Justification.Philosophical Review, 111(1): 6794.Google Scholar
Feltz, A. and Cokely, E. 2009. ‘Do Judgments about Freedom and Responsibility Depend on who you are? Personality Differences in Intuitions about Compatibilism and Incompatibilism.Consciousness and Cognition, 18(1): 356–8.Google Scholar
Gendler, T. and Hawthorne, J. 2005. ‘The Real Guide to Fake Barns: A Catalogue of Gifts for your Epistemic Enemies.Philosophical Studies, 124(3): 331–52.Google Scholar
Goldman, A. 1976. ‘Discrimination and Perceptual Knowledge.Journal of Philosophy, 73: 771–91.Google Scholar
Goldman, A.. 2009. ‘Williamson on Knowledge and Evidence.’ In Greenough, P. & Pritchard, D. (eds), Williamson on Knowledge. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Hawthorne, J. 2004. Knowledge and Lotteries. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Lewis, D. 1996. ‘Elusive Knowledge.Australasian Journal of Philosophy, 74(4): 549–67.Google Scholar
Livengood, J. and Machery, E. 2007. ‘The Folk Probably don't Think what you Think they Think: Experiments on Causation by Absence.Midwest Studies in Philosophy, 31: 107–27.Google Scholar
Luper, S. 2010. ‘The Epistemic Closure Principle.’ The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy (Fall 2010 Edition). http://plato.stanford.edu/archives/fall2010/entries/closure-epistemic/.Google Scholar
Lycan, W. 2006. ‘On the Gettier Problem Problem.’ In Hetherington, S. (ed.), Epistemology Futures, pp. 146168. Oxford: Clarendon Press.Google Scholar
Machery, E. 2011. ‘Thought Experiments and Philosophical Knowledge.Metaphilosophy, 42(3): 191214.Google Scholar
Machery, E., Mallon, R., Nichols, S. and Stich, S. 2004. ‘Semantics, Cross-cultural Style.Cognition, 92: B1B12.Google Scholar
Machery, E., Olivola, C. Y. and De Blanc, M. 2009. ‘Linguistic and Metalinguistic Intuitions in the Philosophy of Language.Analysis, 69: 689–94.Google Scholar
Machery, E., Deutsch, M., Mallon, R., Nichols, S., Sytsma, J. and Stich, S. 2010. ‘Semantic Intuitions: Reply to Lam.Cognition, 117: 361–6.Google Scholar
Mallon, R., Machery, E., Nichols, S. and Stich, S. 2009. ‘Against Arguments from Reference.Philosophy and Phenomenological Research, 79(2): 332–56.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Murray, D., Sytsma, J. and Livengood, J. Forthcoming. ‘God Knows (but does God Believe?).’ Philosophical Studies.Google Scholar
Myers-Schulz, B. and Schwitzgebel, E. Forthcoming. ‘Knowing that P without Believing that P.’ Nous.Google Scholar
Nichols, S., Stich, S. and Weinberg, J. M. 2003. ‘Meta-skepticism: Meditations on Ethno-epistemology.’ In Luper, S. (ed.), The Skeptics, pp. 227247. Aldershot: Ashgate.Google Scholar
Rose, D. and Schaffer, J. Forthcoming. ‘Knowledge entails Dispositional Belief.’ Philosophical Studies.Google Scholar
Stanley, J. 2005. Knowledge and Practical Interests. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Starmans, C. and Friedman, O. 2012. ‘The Folk Conception of Knowledge.Cognition, 124(3): 272–83.Google Scholar
Steup, M. 2008. ‘The Analysis of Knowledge.’ The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy (Fall 2008 Edition). http://plato.stanford.edu/archives/fall2008/entries/knowledge-analysis/.Google Scholar
Stich, S. MS. ‘Experimental Philosophy and the Bankruptcy of the Great Tradition.’Google Scholar
Sytsma, J. and Livengood, J. 2011. ‘A New Perspective Concerning Experiments on Semantic Intuitions.Australasian Journal of Philosophy, 89(2): 315–32.Google Scholar
Sytsma, J. and Machery, E. 2010. ‘Two Conceptions of Subjective Experience.Philosophical Studies, 151(2): 299327.Google Scholar
Sytsma, J., Livengood, J., Sato, R. and Oguchi, M. MS. ‘Gödel in the Land of the Rising Sun.’Google Scholar
Swain, M. 1978. ‘Reasons, Causes, and Knowledge.’ Journal of Philosophy, 75: 229–49.Google Scholar
Swain, S., Alexander, J. and Weinberg, J. M. 2008. ‘The Instability of Philosophical Intuitions: Running Hot and Cold on Truetemp.Philosophy and Phenomenological Research, 76(1): 138–55.Google Scholar
Tobia, K., Buckwalter, W. and Stich, S. 2012. ‘Moral Intuitions: Are Philosophers Experts?Philosophical Psychology, 26(5): 629–38.Google Scholar
Tobia, K., Chapman, G. and Stich, S. 2013. ‘Cleanliness is Next to Morality, Even for Philosophers.Journal of Consciousness Studies, 20(11 & 12): 195204.Google Scholar
Truett, K. R. 1993. ‘Age Differences in Conservatism.Personality and Individual Differences, 14(3): 387506.Google Scholar
Turri, J., Buckwalter, W. and Blouw, P. MS. ‘Knowledge and Luck.’Google Scholar
Waterman, J., Gonnerman, C. and Alexander, J. MS. ‘Infallibilism, Salience, and Cross-cultural Diversity.’Google Scholar
Weinberg, J. M. and Crowley, S. 2010. ‘Loose Constitutivity and Armchair Philosophy.Studia Philosophica Estonica, 2: 177195.Google Scholar
Weinberg, J. M., Nichols, S. and Stich, S. 2001. ‘Normativity and Epistemic Intuitions.Philosophical Topics, 29(1–2): 429–60.Google Scholar
Wright, J. C. 2010. ‘On Intuitional Stability: the Clear, the Strong and the Paradigmatic.Cognition, 115: 491503.Google Scholar
Zamzow, J. and Nichols, S. 2009. ‘Variations in Ethical Intuitions.Philosophical Issues, 19(1): 368–88.CrossRefGoogle Scholar