Hostname: page-component-7c8c6479df-fqc5m Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-03-27T03:36:12.971Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

Ressentiment, Revenge, and Punishment: Origins of the Nietzschean Critique

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  26 January 2009

Abstract

Nietzsche's thinking on justice and punishment explores the motives and forces which lie behind moral concepts and social institutions. His dialogue with several writers of his time is discussed here. Eugen Dühring had argued that a natural feeling of ressentiment against those who have harmed us is the source of the concept of injustice, so that punishment, even in its most impersonal form, is always a form of revenge. In attacking this theory, Nietzsche developed his own powerful critique of moral concepts such as responsibility and guilt. He borrowed his ‘historical’ approach to moral concepts from Paul Ree, who suggested that the utilitarian function of punishment had been obscured by its practice, which appears to be directly linked with moral guilt. Nietzsche responds that punishment has quite different purposes and meanings at different times, so that any single explanation or justification is inadequate. In this way, he rejects the pre-suppositions common to the retributivists and utilitarians of his time.

Type
Research Article
Copyright
Copyright © Cambridge University Press 1997

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

References

1 Scheler, Max, Ressentiment, trans. Holdheim, William W., New York, 1972, p. 43Google Scholar.

2 Dühring, Eugen, Der Werth des Lebens. Eine philosophische Betrachtung, Breslau, 1865, p. VTIIGoogle Scholar; and Cursus der Philosophie als streng wissenschaftlicher Weltanschauung und Lebensgestaltung, Leipzig, 1875, p. 224Google Scholar.

3 Similarly, the British jurist Stephen, James Fitzjames asserted that hatred of wrong-doers is ‘a healthy natural sentiment’ which is, and ought to be, satisfied by legal punishment (A History of the Criminal Law of England, London, 1883, vol. 2, p. 82)Google Scholar. This social institution is, Stephen suggests, to hatred and revenge what marriage is to sexual passion – an analogy repeated by Jacoby, Susan in Wild Justice: The Evolution of Revenge, New York, 1983, pp. 1213Google Scholar.

4 Der Werth des Lebens, p. 21. Cf. Nietzsche, , Kritische Gesamtausgabe: Werke [hereafter KGW], ed. Colli, G. and Montinari, M., Berlin, 1973 –, Band IV/1, p. 217Google Scholar.

5 Kant, Immanuel, The Metaphysics of Morals, trans. McGregor, Mary, Cambridge, 1991, p. 140Google Scholar.

6 Ibid., p. 253.

7 Ibid., p. 141.

8 Der Werth des Lebens, p. 20.

9 Ibid., p. 81.

10 Cursus der Philosopkie, pp. 227–8. Unless otherwise stated, all translations are my own; except that in quoting from the published works of Nietzsche, and from the texts included in The Will to Power, I have used the English translations of Walter Kaufmann and R. J. Hollingdale, with occasional modifications.

11 Ibid., p. 234.

12 Ibid., p. 226.

13 Ibid., p. 226; see also Der Werth des Lebens, p. 78, and KGW IV/1, p. 227.

14 KGW IV/1, p. 256.

15 The Genealogy of Morals, Second Essay, sect. 11.

16 Daybreak, sect. 202.

17 Jacoby, p. 12.

18 Ibid., p. 346.

19 See e.g. Elster, Jon, ‘Norms of Revenge’, Ethics 100 (1990), 862–85CrossRefGoogle Scholar, and Hamlin, Alan P., ‘Rational Revenge’, Ethics 101 (1991), 374–81sCrossRefGoogle Scholar.

20 Jacoby, Susan seems to take this view, writing: ‘On a practical level, the human desire for retribution requires no elaborate philosophical justification’ (Jacoby, p. 9)Google Scholar. Of course, on a practical level, nothing requires an elaborate philosophical justification, or even a modest one; but I assume that Jacoby is making a less general claim.

21 Jacoby, cites a line from The Godfather: ‘Accidents don't happen to people who take accidents as a personal insult’ (Jacoby, p. 1)Google Scholar.

22 The Genealogy of Morals, Second Essay, sect. 11.

23 See e.g. Beyond Good and Evil, sect. 13.

24 The Genealogy of Morals, Second Essay, sect. 6.

25 The Wanderer and his Shadow, sect. 5; also KGW V/l, pp. 537, 562 and 564.

26 Schopenhauer, , The World as Will and Representation, trans. Payne, E. F. J., New York, 1969, vol. 1, p. 348Google Scholar.

27 Ibid., p. 357.

28 See KGW IV/1, pp. 253–4.

29 Thus Spake Zarathustra, ‘On the Tarantulas’.

30 Ibid., ‘On Redemption’.

31 Daybreak, sect. 134. Nietzsche continues: ‘If suffering is here and there indirectly reduced or removed as a consequence of pity, this occasional and on the whole insignifi-cant consequence must not be employed to justify its essential nature, which is, as I have said, harmful.’

32 Thus Spake Zarathustra, ‘On Old and New Tablets’, sect. 3.

33 Ibid., ‘On the Pale Criminal’.

34 Human, All-Too-Human, sect. 39.

35 Daybreak, sect. 252.

36 KGW VIII/3, p. 67 (The Will to Power, sect. 551).

37 KGW VIII/3, p. 65 (The Will to Power, sect. 633).

38 Beyond Good and Evil, sect. 22.

39 KGW VIII/1, p. 136 (The Will to Power, sect. 546). For critiques of the ‘subject’ see KGB VIII/1, pp. 133–4 and p. 323 (The Will to Power, sects. 631 and 481).

40 The Genealogy of Morals, First Essay, sect. 13.

41 Human, All-Too-Human, sect. 39.

42 KGW VIII/2, p. 181 (The Will to Power, sect. 235).

43 KGW VII/1, p. 558.

44 Beyond Good and Evil, sect. 17.

45 Ibid., sect. 20.

46 See e.g. KGW VII/3, p. 382 (The Will to Power, sect. 490).

47 KGW VII/1, p. 412. Cf. ibid., 126.

48 Rée, Paul, Der Ursprung der moralischen Empfindungen, Chemnitz, 1877, p. VIIIGoogle Scholar.

49 Here Rée, is following the starting point of Schopenhauer: see On the Basis of Morality, trans. Payne, E. F. J., Indianapolis and New York, 1965Google Scholar.

50 In Rée's later book on conscience, the same point is made again, but this time credited to Anselm Feuerbach. See Rée, , Die Entstehung des Gewissens, Berlin, 1885, p. 192Google Scholar.

51 Der Ursprung der moralischen Empfindungen, p. 42.

52 Ibid., p. 45.

53 Letter of 10 October 1877; Nietzsche, , Kritische Gesamtausgabe: Briefwechsel [hereafter KGB], ed. Colli, G. and Montinari, M., Berlin, 1975 –, Band 6/2, pp. 718–19Google Scholar.

54 Letter of April 1879; KGB 6/2, p. 1090.

55 Rée, , Die Entstehung des Gewissens, Berlin, 1885, p. 39Google Scholar.

56 Ibid., pp. 42–3.

57 Ibid., p. 108.

58 Ibid., p. 202.

59 Publisher's announcement at the end of Dühring, Eugen, Robert Mayer der Galilei des neunzehnten Jahrhunderts, Chemnitz, 1880Google Scholar.

60 The Genealogy of Morals, II, sect. 12.

61 The Wanderer and His Shadow, sect. 33.

62 Ibid., sect. 77.

63 The Genealogy of Morals, II, sect. 13.