Hostname: page-component-8448b6f56d-dnltx Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-04-18T14:52:41.826Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

DWORKIN'S INTERPRETIVISM AND THE PRAGMATICS OF LEGAL DISPUTES*

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  15 January 2014

David Plunkett
Affiliation:
Dartmouth College, david.plunkett@dartmouth.edu
Timothy Sundell
Affiliation:
University of Kentucky

Abstract

One of Ronald Dworkin's most distinctive claims in legal philosophy is that law is an interpretative concept, a special kind of concept whose correct application depends neither on fixed criteria nor on an instance-identifying decision procedure but rather on the normative or evaluative facts that best justify the total set of practices in which that concept is used. The main argument that Dworkin gives for interpretivism about some concept—law, among many others—is a disagreement-based argument. We argue here that Dworkin's disagreement-based argument relies on a mistaken premise about the nature of disagreement. We propose an alternative analysis of the type of dispute—what we call “seeming variation cases”—that Dworkin uses to motivate the idea of interpretative concepts. We begin by observing that genuine disagreements can be expressed via a range of linguistic mechanisms, many of which do not require that speakers literally assert and deny one and the same proposition. We focus in particular on what we call “metalinguistic negotiations,” disputes in which speakers do not express the same concepts by their words but rather negotiate how words should be used and thereby negotiate which of a range of competing concepts should be used in that context. We claim that this view has quite general theoretical advantages over Dworkin's interpretivism about seeming variation cases and about the relevant class of legal disputes in particular. This paper thus has two interlocking goals: (1) to undermine one of Dworkin's core arguments for interpretivism, and (2) to provide the foundations for a noninterpretivist alternative account of an important class of legal disputes.

Type
Research Article
Copyright
Copyright © Cambridge University Press 2014 

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

Footnotes

*

Thanks to David Braddon-Mitchell, Alexi Burgess, Ronald Dworkin, Andy Egan, Triantafyllos Gkouvas, Sandy Goldberg, Mark Greenberg, Scott Hershovitz, AJ Julius, Frank Jackson, Chris Kennedy, Brian Leiter, Peter Ludlow, Kate Manne, Tristram McPherson, Eliot Michaelson, Daniel Nolan, George Pavlakos, Karl Schafer, François Schroeter, Laura Schroeter, Scott Shapiro, Seana Shiffrin, Alex Silk, Dale Smith, Nicos Stavrapolous, Kevin Toh, Kevin Walton, and Pekka Väyrynen. Versions of this paper were presented to audiences at the Julius Stone Institute of Jurisprudence at the University of Sydney School of Law, the Legal Theory Workshop at the University of Melbourne School of Law, the Centre for Law and Cosmopolitan Values at the University of Antwerp, the Jurisprudence Discussion Group at Oxford University, and the 2012 Inland Northwest Philosophy Conference on Pragmatism, Law, and Language. Thanks to everyone who participated in those sessions for their helpful questions and comments.

References

WORKS CITED

Barker, Chris. 2002. “The Dynamics of Vagueness.” Linguistics and Philosophy 25:136.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Barker, Chris. 2013. “Negotiating Taste.” Inquiry 56 (2–3):240257.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Burgess, Alexis, and Plunkett, David. 2013a. “Conceptual Ethics I.” Philosophy Compass 8 (12):10911101.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Burgess, Alexis, and Plunkett, David. 2013b. “Conceptual Ethics II.” Philosophy Compass 8 (12):11011110.Google Scholar
Chalmers, David J. 2011. “Verbal Disputes.” Philosophical Review 120 (4):515566.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Chierchia, Gennaro. 2004. “Polarity Phenomena and the Syntax/Pragmatics Interface.” In Belletti, A., ed., Structures and Beyond (Oxford: Oxford University Press).Google Scholar
Dworkin, Ronald. 1986. Law's Empire (Cambridge, MA: Belknap Press).Google Scholar
Dworkin, Ronald. 2006. “Response.” In Hershovitz, S., ed., Exploring Law's Empire: The Jurisprudence of Ronald Dworkin (Oxford: New York: Oxford University Press).Google Scholar
Dworkin, Ronald. 2011. Justice for Hedgehogs (Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press).Google Scholar
Egan, Andy. 2010. “Disputing about Taste.” In Feldman, R. and Warfield, T., eds., Disagreement (Oxford: Oxford University Press).Google Scholar
Gibbard, Allan. 1990. Wise Choices, Apt Feelings: A Theory of Normative Judgment (Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press).CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Gibbard, Allan. 2003. Thinking How to Live (Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press).Google Scholar
Greenberg, Mark. 2006. “How Facts Make Law.” In Hershovitz, S., ed., Exploring Law's Empire: The Jurisprudence of Ronald Dworkin (Oxford: New York: Oxford University Press).Google Scholar
Greenberg, Mark. 2006. “Hartian Positivism and Normative Facts: How Facts Make Law II.” In Hershovitz, S., ed., Exploring Law's Empire: The Jurisprudence of Ronald Dworkin (Oxford: New York: Oxford University Press).Google Scholar
Greenberg, Mark. 2011. “The Standard Picture and Its Discontents.” In Green, L. and Leiter, B., eds., Oxford Studies in Philosophy of Law. Volume 1 (Oxford: Oxford University Press).Google Scholar
Grice, H. Paul. 1989. “Logic and Conversation.” In Studies in the Way of Words (Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press).Google Scholar
Jackson, Frank. 1998. From Metaphysics to Ethics: A Defence of Conceptual Analysis (Oxford: Clarendon Press).Google Scholar
Kaplan, David. 1989. “Demonstratives: An Essay on the Semantics, Logic, Metaphysics, and Epistemology of Demonstratives.” In Almog, Joseph, Perry, John, and Wettstein, Howard, eds., Themes from Kaplan (Oxford: Oxford University Press).Google Scholar
Kennedy, Chris. 2007. “Vagueness and Grammar: The Semantics of Relative and Absolute Gradable Predicates. Linguistics and Philosophy 30 (1):145.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Leiter, Brian. 2009. “Explaining Theoretical Disagreement.” University of Chicago Law Review 76 (3):12151250.Google Scholar
Lewis, David. 1983. “New Work for a Theory of Universals.” Australasian Journal of Philosophy 61 (4):343377.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Ludlow, Peter. 2008. “Cheap Contextualism.” Philosophical Issues 18:104129.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Margolis, Eric, and Laurence, Stephen. 1999. Concepts: Core Readings (Cambridge, MA: MIT Press).Google Scholar
Plunkett, David. 2012. “A Positivist Route for Explaining How Facts Make Law.” Legal Theory 18 (2):139207.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Plunkett, David, and Sundell, Timothy. 2014. “Antipositivist Arguments from Legal Thought and Talk: The Metalinguistic Response.” In Hubbs, G. and Lind, D., eds., Pragmatism, Law, and Language (New York: Routledge).Google Scholar
Plunkett, David, and Sundell, Timothy. 2013. “Disagreement and the Semantics of Normative and Evaluative Terms.” Philosophers’ Imprint 13 (23):137.Google Scholar
Shapiro, Scott. 2011. Legality (Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press).CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Sider, Theodore. 2012. Writing the Book of the World (Oxford: Oxford University Press).Google Scholar
Smith, Michael. 1994. The Moral Problem (Cambridge, UK: Blackwell).Google Scholar
Sundell, Timothy. 2011. “Disagreement, Error, and an Alternative to Reference Magnetism.” Australasian Journal of Philosophy 90 (4):743759.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Sundell, Timothy. 2011. “Disagreements about Taste.” Philosophical Studies 155 (2):267288.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Toh, Kevin. 2005. “Hart's Expressivism and His Benthamite Project.” Legal Theory 11 (2):75123.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Toh, Kevin. 2011. “Legal Judgments as Plural Acceptances of Norms.” In Green, L. and Leiter, B., eds., Oxford Studies in Philosophy of Law. Volume 1 (Oxford: Oxford University Press).Google Scholar
U.S. Department of Justice, Office of the Assistant Attorney General. 2002. Memorandum for Alberto R. Gonzales, Counsel to the President, Re: Standards of Conduct for Interrogation under 18 U.S.C. secs. 2340–2340A.Google Scholar
United Nations, General Assembly. 1984. Convention Against Torture and Other Cruel, Inhuman or Degrading Treatment or Punishment. Opened for signature December 10, 1984, (entered into force June 26, 1987). United Nations Treaty Series 1465.Google Scholar
Wedgwood, Ralph. 2007. The Nature of Normativity (Oxford: Oxford University Press).CrossRefGoogle Scholar