Hostname: page-component-7c8c6479df-27gpq Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-03-28T19:31:11.681Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

A Genealogy of Rational Choice: Rationalism, Elitism, and Democracy

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  09 October 2008

J. S. Maloy*
Affiliation:
Oklahoma State University
*
J. S. Maloy, Department of Political Science, Oklahoma State University, 519 Math Sciences Building, Stillwater, Oklahoma, USA74078, maloyj@okstate.edu.

Abstract

Abstract. Unlike previous methodological debates in political science, the recent rational choice controversy has excluded consideration of normative questions altogether. These can be recovered, in part, through a genealogy of counter-utopian democratic theory which connects modern rational choice theory to the fin-de-siècle sociology of elites via the mediating figure of Schumpeter. The family resemblances include the aspiration toward a pure science of society, the search for a “realistic” theory of democratic politics, and the shading of an empirical proposition about elite domination into a normative celebration. Though democratic theorists have learned much from the counter-utopian tradition generally, both sides of the rational choice controversy have failed to take seriously the elitists' recognition of the ineluctable normative and ideological dimensions of social research.

Résumé. Les débats récents sur le choix rationnel, à contre-pied d'autres disputes méthodologiques en science politique, ont exclu les questions normatives. Ces questions peuvent se rétablir, en partie, par l'intermédiaire d'une généalogie contre-utopiste de la théorie démocratique, qui lie la théorie moderne du choix rationnel au retour de la sociologie élitiste de fin de siècle, avec le personnage de Schumpeter comme médiateur. Les ressemblances familiales portent l'aspiration à une science pure de la société, la recherche d'une théorie «réaliste» de la démocratie et la transition d'une proposition empirique sur la domination des élites vers une célébration normative. Bien que les théoriciens démocratiques aient beaucoup appris de la tradition contre-utopiste, aucune des deux parties du débat sur le choix rationnel n'a pris en compte la reconnaissance élitiste des aspects idéologiques inévitables de la recherche sociale.

Type
Research Article
Copyright
Copyright © Canadian Political Science Association 2008

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

References

Albertoni, E. 1992. “The Origins and Development of Political Elitism.” In Elitism and Democracy: Mosca, Pareto, and Michels, ed. Ghiringhelli, R.. Milan: Cisalpino.Google Scholar
Allen, R.L. 1991. Opening Doors: The Life and Work of Joseph Schumpeter. 2 vols. New Brunswick, NJ: Transaction Publishers.Google Scholar
Amadae, S.M. 2003. Rationalizing Capitalist Democracy: The Cold War Origins of Rational Choice Liberalism. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.Google Scholar
Andic, F.M., and Andic, S.. 1985. “An Exploration into Fiscal Sociology.” Finanzarchiv 43: 454–69.Google Scholar
Aristotle. 1998. Politics, trans. Reeve, C.D.C.. Indianapolis: Hackett.Google Scholar
Arrow, K.J. 1963 (1951). Social Choice and Individual Values. 2nded.New York: John Wiley.Google Scholar
Bachrach, P. 1967. The Theory of Democratic Elitism: A Critique. Boston: Little, Brown.Google Scholar
Ball, T. 1988. Transforming Political Discourse. Oxford: Basil Blackwell.Google Scholar
Barry, B. 1978. Sociologists, Economists, and Democracy. London: Cikkuer-Macmillan.Google Scholar
Bates, R.H., Greif, A., Levi, M., Rosenthal, J.-L. and Weingast, B.. 1998. Analytic Narratives. Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press.Google Scholar
Bottomore, T.B. 1992. Between Marginalism and Marxism: The Economic Sociology of J.A. Schumpeter. New York: St Martin's Press.Google Scholar
Buchanan, J.M., and Tullock, G.. 1962. The Calculus of Consent. Ann Arbor, MI: University of Michigan Press.Google Scholar
Burnham, J. 1943. The Machiavellians, Defenders of Freedom. New York: John Day.Google Scholar
Cook, K.S., Hardin, R. and Levi, M.. 2005. Co-Operation without Trust? New York: Russell Sage Foundation.Google Scholar
Dahl, R.A. 1965. A Preface to Democratic Theory. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.Google Scholar
Downs, A. 1957. An Economic Theory of Democracy. New York: Addison-Wesley.Google Scholar
Duncan, G., and Lukes, S.. 1963. “The New Democracy.” Political Studies 11: 156–77.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Engelmann, S. 2003. Imagining Interest in Political Thought: Origins of Economic Rationality. Durham, NC: Duke University Press.Google Scholar
Finocchiaro, M. 1999. Beyond Right and Left: Democratic Elitism in Mosca and Gramsci. New Haven, CT: Yale University Press.Google Scholar
Force, P. 2003. Self-Interest before Adam Smith: A Genealogy of Economic Science. Cambridge, UK: Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Friedman, J., ed. 1996. The Rational Choice Controversy. New Haven, CT: Yale University Press.Google Scholar
Friedrich, C.J. 1942. The New Belief in the Common Man. Boston: Little, Brown & Co.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Gerring, J., and Yesnowitz, J.. 2006. “A Normative Turn in Political Science?Polity 38: 101–33.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Green, D., and Shapiro, I.. 1994. Pathologies of Rational Choice Theory. New Haven, CT: Yale University Press.Google Scholar
Hanusch, H., ed. 1999. The Legacy of Joseph A. Schumpeter. 2 vols. Northampton, MA: Elgar.Google Scholar
Hardin, R. 2002. “Whither Political Science?PS: Political Science and Politics 35: 183–86.Google Scholar
Hauptmann, E. 1997. Putting Choice before Democracy. Albany, NY: SUNY Press.Google Scholar
Lipset, S.M. 1960. Political Man: The Social Bases of Politics. New York: Doubleday.Google Scholar
Mackie, G. 2003. Democracy Defended. Cambridge, UK: Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
März, E. 1991. Joseph Schumpeter: Scholar, Teacher, and Politician. New Haven, CT: Yale University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Medearis, J. 2001. Joseph Schumpeter's Two Theories of Democracy. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Meisel, J.H. 1962. The Myth of the Ruling Class. Ann Arbor, MI: University of Michigan Press.Google Scholar
Meisel, J.H., ed. 1965. Mosca and Pareto. Englewood Cliffs, NJ: Prentice Hall.Google Scholar
Michels, R. 1915. Political Parties: A Sociological Study of the Oligarchical Trends of Modern Democracy, trans. C. Paul, E. and C. Paul, E.. New York: Dover Publications.Google Scholar
Mosca, G. 1939. The Ruling Class, trans. Kahn, H.D., ed. Livingston, A.. New York: McGraw Hill.Google Scholar
Murphy, J.B. 1996. “Rational Choice as Social Physics.” In The Rational Choice Controversy, ed. Friedman, J.. New Haven, CT: Yale University Press.Google Scholar
Olson, M. 1965. The Logic of Collective Action. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Oren, I. 2003. Our Enemies and US: America's Rivalries and the Making of Political Science. Ithaca, NY: Cornell University Press.Google Scholar
Oren, I. 2006. “Can Political Science Emulate the Natural Sciences? The Problem of Self-Disconfirming Analysis.” Polity 38: 72100.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Palumbo, A., and Scott, A.. 2003. “Weber and Durkheim.” In The Cambridge History of Twentieth-Century Political Thought, ed. Ball, T. and Bellamy, R.. Cambridge, UK: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Pareto, V. 1980. Compendium of General Sociology, ed. Farina, G. and Abbott, E.. Minneapolis: University of Minnesota Press.Google Scholar
Pateman, C. 1970. Participation and Democratic Theory. Cambridge, UK: Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Ricci, D.M. 1970. “Democracy Attenuated: Schumpeter, the Process Theory, and American Democratic Thought.” Journal of Politics 32: 239–67.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Riker, W.H. 1962. The Theory of Political Coalitions. New Haven, CT: Yale University Press.Google Scholar
Riker, W.H. 1982. Liberalism against Populism: A Confrontation between the Theory of Democracy and the Theory of Social Choice. San Francisco: Waveland Press.Google Scholar
Runciman, W. 1969. Social Science and Political Theory. 2nded.Cambridge, UK: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Sartori, G. 1965. Democratic Theory. New York: Praeger.Google Scholar
Schumpeter, J.A. 1942. Capitalism, Socialism, and Democracy. New York: Routledge.Google Scholar
Schumpeter, J.A. 1951 (1949). “Vilfredo Pareto.” In Ten Great Economists. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Shapiro, I. 2005. The Flight from Reality in the Human Sciences. Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press.Google Scholar
Skinner, Q. 1973. “The Empirical Theorists of Democracy and Their Critics: A Plague on Both Their Houses.” Political Theory 1: 287306.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Swedberg, R. 1989. “Joseph A. Schumpeter and the Tradition of Economic Sociology.” Journal of Institutional and Theoretical Economics 145: 508–24.Google Scholar
Walker, J.L. 1966. “A Critique of the Elitist Theory of Democracy.” American Political Science Review 60: 283–95.Google Scholar
Weintraub, E.R. 1992. Toward a History of Game Theory. Durham, NC: Duke University Press.Google Scholar