Hostname: page-component-8448b6f56d-cfpbc Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-04-17T19:14:11.265Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

Political Legitimacy in the Real Normative World: The Priority of Morality and the Autonomy of the Political

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  04 June 2013

Abstract

According to what has recently been labeled ‘political realism’ in political theory, ‘political moralists’ such as Rawls and Dworkin misconstrue the political domain by presuming that morality has priority over politics, thus overlooking that the political is an autonomous domain with its own distinctive conditions and normative sources. Political realists argue that this presumption, commonly referred to as the ‘ethics first premise’, has to be abandoned in order to properly theorize a normative conception of political legitimacy. This article critically examines two features of political realism, which so far have received too little systematic philosophical analysis: the political realist critique of political moralism and the challenges facing political realism in its attempt to offer an alternative account of political legitimacy. Two theses are defended. First, to the extent that proponents of political realism wish to hold onto a normative conception of political legitimacy, refuting wholesale the ethics first premise leads to a deadlock, since it throws the baby out with the bathwater by closing the normative space upon which their account of political legitimacy relies. This is called the ‘necessity thesis’: all coherent and plausible conceptions of political legitimacy must hold onto the ethics first premise. Secondly, accepting this premise – and thus defending an ethics first view – does not entail that the political domain must be seen as a subordinate arena for the application of moral principles, that political normativity is reduced to morality or that morality trumps other reasons in political decision making, as claimed by political realists. Rather, the ethics first view is compatible with an autonomous political domain that makes room for an account of political legitimacy that is defined by and substantiated from sources of normativity specifically within the political. This is called the ‘compatibility thesis’.

Type
Articles
Copyright
Copyright © Cambridge University Press 2013 

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

Footnotes

*

Department of Government, Uppsala University (email: eva.erman@statsvet.uu.se) and Department of Philosophy, Royal Institute of Technology (email: nmoller@kth.se). We owe special thanks to Richard North, Thomas Christiano, Terry Macdonald, Bob Goodin, Andrew Williams, Laura Valentini, Rainer Forst, John Cantwell and Christine Chwaszcza for comments on earlier drafts of this article. Thanks also to the journal's editors and anonymous reviewers. In addition, Eva Erman wishes to thank the participants at the Authority of Global Institutions workshop in Barcelona (June 2012), and Samantha Besson, José Luis Martí and Andrew Williams for inviting her; as well as the participants at the How Can International Political Theory Get “Real”? workshop in Melbourne (March 2012) and the Critical Theory Roundtable in Prague (May 2012). Moreover, she wishes to thank Riksbankens Jubileumsfond (RJ) for financing the Transdemos Programme. Niklas Möller thanks the Swedish Research Council Formas for its generous funding of this research.

References

Bavister-Gould, Alex. 2011. Bernard Williams: Political Realism and the Limits of Legitimacy. European Journal of Philosophy. Early online view. doi:10.1111/j.1468-0378.2011.00464.x.Google Scholar
Bellamy, Richard. 2010. Dirty Hands and Clean Gloves: Liberal Ideals and Real Politics. European Journal of Political Theory 9:412430.Google Scholar
Brandom, Robert. 1994. Making it Explicit. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.Google Scholar
Brink, David. 1998. Moral Realism and the Foundations of Ethics. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Brink, David. 2001. Realism, Naturalism, and Moral Semantics. Social Philosophy & Policy 18:154176.Google Scholar
Dahl, Robert. 1989. Democracy and its Critics. New Haven: Yale University Press.Google Scholar
Erman, Eva. 2009. What is Wrong with Agonistic Pluralism? Reflections on Conflict in Democratic Theory. Philosophy & Social Criticism 35:10391062.Google Scholar
Erman, Eva Möller, Niklas. 2013. Three Failed Charges Against Ideal Theory. Social Theory & Practice 39:1944.Google Scholar
Estlund, David. 2008. Democratic Authority: A Philosophical Framework. New Jersey: Princeton University Press.Google Scholar
Estlund, David. 2011. Human Nature and the Limits (If Any) of Political Philosophy. Philosophy & Public Affairs 39:207237.Google Scholar
Farrelly, Colin. 2007. Justice in Ideal Theory: A Refutation. Political Studies 55:844864.Google Scholar
Foot, Philippa. 1959. Moral Beliefs. Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society 59:83104.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Galston, William. 2010. Realism in Political Theory. European Journal of Political Theory 9:385411.Google Scholar
Geuss, Raymond. 2008. Philosophy and Real Politics. Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press.Google Scholar
Gibbard, Allan. 2003. Thinking How to Live. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.Google Scholar
Habermas, Jürgen. 1996. Between Facts and Norms: Contributions to a Discourse Theory of Law and Democracy. Translated by William Rehg. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.Google Scholar
Honig, Bonnie. 1993. Political Theory and the Displacement of Politics. Ithaca, NY: Cornell University Press.Google Scholar
Hooker, Brad Little, Margaret. 2000. Moral Particularism. Oxford: Clarendon Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Horton, John. 2010. Realism, Liberal Moralism and a Political Theory of Modus Vivendi. European Journal of Political Theory 9:431448.Google Scholar
Hume, David. 1998. An Enquiry Concerning the Principles of Morals, edited by Tom Beauchamp. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Hurka, Thomas. 2009. Review of Geuss's Philosophy and Real Politics. Notre Dame Philosophical Reviews No. 1, January. Available from http://ndpr.nd.edu/news/23887-philosophy-and-real-politics/, accessed 13 April 2013.Google Scholar
Jackson, Frank. 1998. From Ethics to Metaphysics: A Defence of Conceptual Analysis. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Mason, Andrew. 2010. Rawlsian Theory and the Circumstances of Politics. Political Theory 38:658683.Google Scholar
Mason, Andrew. 2012. Legitimacy and Disagreement: A Reply to Sleat. Political Theory 40:657662.Google Scholar
Mills, Charles. 2005. ‘Ideal Theory’ as Ideology. Hypathia 20:165184.Google Scholar
Mouffe, Chantal. 2005. On the Political. London: Routledge.Google Scholar
Newey, Glen. 2010. Two Dogmas of Liberalism. European Journal of Political Theory 9:449465.Google Scholar
Parfit, Derek. 1997. Reasons and Motivation. Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society, (suppl. 71):99130.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Parfit, Derek. 2011. On What Matters, Vol. I. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Philp, Mark. 2007. Political Conduct. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.Google Scholar
Philp, Mark. 2010. What is to be Done? Political Theory and Political Realism. European Journal of Political Theory 9:466484.Google Scholar
Philp, Mark. 2012. Realism without Illusions. Political Theory 40:629649.Google Scholar
Rachels, James. 1999. The Elements of Moral Philosophy. New York: McGraw-Hill.Google Scholar
Ross, William D. 1930. The Right and the Good. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Rossi, Enzo. 2010. Reality and Imagination in Political Theory and Practice: On Raymond Geuss’ Realism. European Journal of Political Theory 9:204212.Google Scholar
Rossi, Enzo. 2012. Justice, Legitimacy and (Normative) Authority for Political Realists. Critical Review of International Social and Political Philosophy 15:149164.Google Scholar
Sangiovanni, Andrea. 2008. Justice and the Priority of Politics to Morality. Journal of Political Philosophy 16:137164.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Sangiovanni, Andrea. 2011. Global Justice and the Moral Arbitrariness of Birth. The Monist 94:571583.Google Scholar
Scanlon, Thomas. 1998. What We Owe To Each Other. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.Google Scholar
Sen, Amartya. 2009. The Idea of Justice. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.Google Scholar
Sidgwick, Henry. 1874. The Methods of Ethics. London: Macmillan.Google Scholar
Simmons, John. 2010. Ideal and Nonideal Theory. Philosophy & Public Affairs 38:536.Google Scholar
Sleat, Matt. 2010. Bernard Williams and the Possibility of a Realist Political Theory. European Journal of Political Theory 9:485503.Google Scholar
Sleat, Matt. 2012. Legitimacy in a Non-Ideal Key: A Critical Response to Andrew Mason. Political Theory 40:650656.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Stears, Marc. 2007. Review Article: Liberalism and the Politics of Compulsion. British Journal of Political Science 37:505531.Google Scholar
Valentini, Laura. 2009. On the Apparent Paradox of Ideal Theory. The Journal of Political Philosophy 17:332355.Google Scholar
Waldron, Jeremy. 1999. Law and Disagreement. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Walzer, Michael. 1984. Spheres of Justice. New York: Basic Books.Google Scholar
Wedgwood, Ralph. 2001. Conceptual Role Semantics for Moral Terms. Philosophical Review 110:130.Google Scholar
Wiggins, David. 1990. Moral Cognitivism, Moral Relativism and Motivating Moral Beliefs. Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society 91:6185.Google Scholar
Williams, Bernard. 1985. Ethics and the Limits of Philosophy. London: Fontana.Google Scholar
Williams, Bernard. 2005. In the Beginning Was the Deed: Realism and Moralism in Political Argument, edited by Geoffrey Hawthorn. Oxford: Princeton University Press.Google Scholar