Hostname: page-component-7c8c6479df-r7xzm Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-03-29T05:53:01.180Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

Pathways to global democracy? Escaping the statist imaginary

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  08 February 2013

Abstract

Critics of global democracy have often claimed that the social and political conditions necessary for democracy to function are not met at the global level, and are unlikely to be in the foreseeable future. Such claims are usually developed with reference to national democratic institutions, and the social conditions within national democratic societies that have proved important in sustaining them. Although advocates of global democracy have contested such sceptical conclusions, they have tended to accept the method of reasoning from national to global contexts on which they are based. This article critiques this method of argument, showing that it is both highly idealised in its characterisation of national democratic practice, and overly state-centric in its assumptions about possible institutional forms that global democracy might take. We suggest that if aspiring global democrats – and their critics – are to derive useful lessons from social struggles to create and sustain democracy within nation states, a less idealised and institutionally prescriptive approach to drawing global lessons from national experience is required. We illustrate one possible such approach with reference to cases from both national and global levels, in which imperfect yet meaningful democratic practices have survived under highly inhospitable – and widely varying – conditions.

Type
Articles
Copyright
Copyright © British International Studies Association 2013 

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

References

1 Miller, D., ‘Democracy's Domain’, Philosophy and Public Affairs, 37 (2009), p. 228CrossRefGoogle Scholar.

2 Buchanan, A. and Keohane, Robert O., ‘The Legitimacy of Global Governance Institutions’, Ethics and International Affairs, 20 (2006), pp. 405–37CrossRefGoogle Scholar.

3 Koenig-Archibugi, M., ‘Is Global Democracy Possible?’, European Journal of International Relations, 7 (2010), pp. 519–42Google Scholar; Archibugi, D., Koenig-Archibugi, M., and Marchetti, R., Global Democracy: Normative and Empirical Perspectives (Cambridge Cambridge University Press, 2011)CrossRefGoogle Scholar. Until very recently, much of the literature on global democracy has been preoccupied with debates about whether global democracy is desirable, and if so, what models of global democracy should be supported. See, for example, Dryzek, J. S., ‘Transnational Democracy’, Journal of Political Philosophy, 7 (1999), pp. 3051CrossRefGoogle Scholar; Kuper, A., Democracy Beyond Borders: Justice and Representation in Global Institutions (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2004)CrossRefGoogle Scholar; Marchetti, R., Global Democracy: For and Against: Ethical Theory, Institutional Design and Social Struggles (Abingdon: Routledge, 2008)Google Scholar.

4 Dahl, R. A., Democracy and its critics (New Haven: Yale University Press, 1989), pp. viii, 397Google Scholar; Buchanan, A., and Keohane, Robert O., ‘The Legitimacy of Global Governance Institutions’, Ethics and International Affairs, 20 (2006), pp. 405–37CrossRefGoogle Scholar; D. Miller, ‘Democracy's Domain’.

5 M. Koenig-Archibugi, ‘Is Global Democracy Possible?’, pp. 519–42. This is a somewhat subtle point, and of course there are important exceptions. Goodhart, M., ‘Human Rights and Global Democracy’, Ethics and International Affairs, 22 (2008), p. 401CrossRefGoogle Scholar, for example, is explicit in critiquing a statist view of democracy. Similarly, Held, D., Democracy and the Global Order: From the Modern State to Cosmopolitan Governance (Cambridge: Polity Press, 1995)Google Scholar is very explicit in critiquing state-centric assumptions, and pointing to the need for institutional models that fall outside this model. Nonetheless, most concrete reform proposals he outlines resemble familiar state centred institutional forms in important respects, thereby tending in practice to reinforce rather than challenge this statist tendency in the literature.

6 See for example Koenig-Archibugi, M., ‘Is Global Democracy Possible?’, European Journal of International Relations, 7 (2010), pp. 519–42Google Scholar.

7 Buchanan, A. and Keohane, Robert O., ‘The Legitimacy of Global Governance Institutions’, Ethics and International Affairs, 20 (2006), p. 417CrossRefGoogle Scholar.

8 Miller, D., ‘Against Global Democracy’, in Breen, K. and O'Neill, S. (eds), After the Nation: Critical Reflections on Post-Nationalism (Basingstoke: Palgrave Macmillan (2010), p. 148Google Scholar.

9 A. Buchanan and Robert O. Keohane, ‘The Legitimacy of Global Governance Institutions’, pp. 405–37; List, C. and Koenig-Archibugi, M., ‘Can There Be a Global Demos? An Agency-Based Approach’, Philosophy and Public Affairs, 38 (2010), pp. 76110CrossRefGoogle Scholar.

10 This distinction is often made with reference to the kratos and demos. We prefer not to use these terms here. The kratos invokes and implies many of the state-like institutional assumptions that we critique in Part II. The demos – understood narrowly as a ‘collection of individuals’ (List and Koenig-Archibugi, ‘Can There Be a Global Demos? An Agency-Based Approach’) is too narrow a concept for grasping the relevant features of the social foundations that enable and constrain the emergence and sustainability of democratic global institutions. To understand the relevant ‘qualities and relationships’ characterising a demos (in the words of Miller, ‘Democracy's Domain’), it is necessary to analyse broader features of the social order in which these individuals and their relationships are constituted, as we do in Part III.

11 The notion of a ‘threshold’ where a set of practices or institutions embodying democratic values can properly be called ‘Democracy’ is often invoked, though rarely theorised explicitly. See, for example, Koenig-Archibugi, M., ‘Is Global Democracy Possible?’, European Journal of International Relations, 7 (2010), p. 3Google Scholar; and Tallberg, J. and Uhlin, A., ‘Civil Society and Global Democracy: An Assessment’, in Archibugi, D., Koenig-Archibugi, M., and Marchetti, R. (eds), Global Democracy: Normative and Empirical Perspectives (Cambridge Cambridge University Press, 2011), p. 227Google Scholar.

12 Sen, A., ‘What do we want from a theory of justice?’, The Journal of Philosophy, 103 (2006), p. 216CrossRefGoogle Scholar.

13 Macdonald, T., Global Stakeholder Democracy: Power and Representation Beyond Liberal States (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2008)CrossRefGoogle Scholar; Goodhart, M., ‘Human Rights and Global Democracy’, Ethics and International Affairs, 22 (2008), p. 401CrossRefGoogle Scholar.

14 Clearly, given our desire to avoid building institutionally specific assumptions into our democratic concepts, these principles of political control and political equality cannot themselves be understood in institutionally specific ways. We understand these principles in a broadly conventional way to require that indivdiuals within a given democratic polity have equal influence over the systems of public decisions that affect them. However, we make no assumptions about the institutional character of relevant public decision making systems, or the instituional modalities through which such equal influence is exercised.

15 Goodin, R., ‘Global Democracy: In the Beginning’, International Theory, 2 (2010), pp. 175209CrossRefGoogle Scholar.

16 We therefore recognise that the social practices we are describing as democratic are not exclusively or distinctively democratic, and could plausibly be otherwise interpreted, for example as instances of transnational accountability Keohane, R. O. and Nye, J. S., ‘Democracy, Accountability and Global Governance’, in Held, D. and Koenig-Archibugi, M. (eds), Global Governance and Public Accountability (New Jersey: Wiley-Blackwell, 2004)Google Scholar; as global administrative law Kingsbury, B., ‘Global Governance as Administration – National and Transnational Approaches to Global Administrative Law’, Law and Contemporary Problems, 68 (2005)Google Scholar, or as institutions protective of rights Macdonald, T., ‘The Liberal Battlefields of Global Business Regulation’, Ethics and Global Politics, 3 (2010), pp. 303–24CrossRefGoogle Scholar. Indeed, these distinct practices often develop through deeply interconnected processes, as they have done within more fully blown ‘democracies’ at the national level. Moreover, they are often grounded in common values, and can support each other functionally in important respects Goodhart, M., Democracy as Human Rights: Freedom and Equality in the Age of Globalization (Routledge, 2005)Google Scholar; Christiano, T., ‘An Instrumental Argument for a Human Right to Democracy’, Philosophy and Public Affairs, 39 (2011), pp. 142–76CrossRefGoogle Scholar.

17 R. A. Dahl, Democracy and its critics.

18 Macdonald, T. and Macdonald, K., ‘Non-Electoral Accountability in Global Politics: Strengthening Democratic Control within the Global Garment Industry’, European Journal of International Law, 12 (2006), pp. 89119CrossRefGoogle Scholar.

19 Sometimes this is implicit, as in relation to Dahl's critiques of trade-offs between citizen participation and the scale of government (R. A. Dahl, Democracy and its critics). At other times this is explicit, as in the case of M. Koenig-Archibugi, ‘Is Global Democracy Possible?’

20 Christiano, T., ‘A Democratic Theory of Territory and Some Puzzles about Global Democracy’, Journal of Social Philosophy, 37 (2006), pp. 81107, p. 12CrossRefGoogle Scholar.

21 Snider, L., ‘Accommodating Power: the ‘Common Sense’ of Regulators’, Social Legal Studies, 18 (2009), pp. 179–97CrossRefGoogle Scholar, Koenig-Archibugi, M., ‘Is Global Democracy Possible?’, European Journal of International Relations, 7 (2010), pp. 519–42, p. 9Google Scholar.

22 See, for example, Held, D. and Koenig-Archibugi, M., Taming globalization: frontiers of governance (Cambridge: Polity Press, 2003)Google Scholar.

23 Nagel, T., ‘The Problem of Global Justice’, Philosophy and Public Affairs, 33 (2005)CrossRefGoogle Scholar.

24 A. Buchanan and Robert O. Keohane, ‘The Legitimacy of Global Governance Institutions’, p. 416. See also Goodin, R., ‘Global Democracy: In the Beginning’, International Theory, 2 (2010), pp. 175209, p. 200CrossRefGoogle Scholar.

25 R. Goodin, ‘Global Democracy: In the Beginning’, p. 201.

26 C. List and M. Koenig-Archibugi, ‘Can There Be a Global Demos? An Agency-Based Approach’, p. 92.

27 C. List and M. Koenig-Archibugi, ‘Can There Be a Global Demos? An Agency-Based Approach’.

28 T. Christiano, ‘A Democratic Theory of Territory and Some Puzzles about Global Democracy’. For example, on p. 94 he says that the achievements of liberal democratic societies are ‘highly imperfect and only partly living up to the ideals of democracy’.

29 See, for example, C. List and M. Koenig-Archibugi, ‘Can There Be a Global Demos? An Agency-Based Approach’, pp. 87–8.

30 Crozier, M. and Little, A., ‘Democratic Voice: Popular Sovereignty in Conditions of Pluralisation’, Australian Journal of Political Science, 47 (2012), pp. 333–46CrossRefGoogle Scholar.

31 Geuss, R., Philosophy and Real Politics (Princeton: Princeton University Press, 2008)CrossRefGoogle Scholar.

32 R. Goodin, ‘Global Democracy: In the Beginning’.

33 For example, M. Koenig-Archibugi, ‘Is Global Democracy Possible?’, quotes Michael Doyle saying that ‘no strong version of global democracy is viable at the present time’. Similarly, Miller, D., ‘Against Global Democracy’, in Breen, K. and O'Neill, S. (eds), After the Nation: Critical Reflections on Post-Nationalism (Basingstoke: Palgrave Macmillan, 2010)Google Scholar discusses some dimensions on which democracy might be weaker or stronger, depending on the extent of political control, political equality, and the scope of issues brought into democratic decision making in a given case.

34 Schweller cited in M. Koenig-Archibugi, ‘Is Global Democracy Possible?’

35 Similar analysis has been developed in the literature on global justice, where scholars have sought to identify the kinds of background social conditions on which obligations of justice depend (for example, Barry, C. and Valentini, L., ‘Egalitarian challenges to global egalitarianism: A critique’, Review of International Studies, 35 (2009), pp. 485512CrossRefGoogle Scholar; Pevnick, R., ‘Political Coercion and the Scope of Distributive Justice’, Political Studies, 56 (2008), pp. 399413CrossRefGoogle Scholar.

36 C. List and M. Koenig-Archibugi, ‘Can There Be a Global Demos? An Agency-Based Approach’.

37 D. Miller, ‘Democracy's Domain’.

38 Ibid.

39 Ibid.

40 Cited in Barry, C. and Valentini, L., ‘Egalitarian challenges to global egalitarianism: A critique’, Review of International Studies, 35 (2009), p. 508CrossRefGoogle Scholar.

41 D. Miller, ‘Democracy's Domain’; M. Koenig-Archibugi, ‘Is Global Democracy Possible?’

42 D. Miller, ‘Democracy's Domain’.

43 Miller, D., ‘Against Global Democracy’, in Breen, K. and O'Neill, S. (eds), After the Nation: Critical Reflections on Post-Nationalism (Basingstoke: Palgrave Macmillan, 2010)Google Scholar.

44 Cited in M. Koenig-Archibugi, ‘Is Global Democracy Possible?’

45 T. Christiano, ‘A Democratic Theory of Territory and Some Puzzles about Global Democracy’.

46 The common world is distinguished from ‘partial associations’ (p. 86) in which there is no reason to think that the interests of the members are equally at stake in that association.

47 M. Koenig-Archibugi, ‘Is Global Democracy Possible?’ comes to a similar conclusion.

48 In making this point, these cases serve a purely illustrative purpose, and we could have chosen other cases with these same characteristics to make our point. However we certainly don't claim that these cases are ‘representative’ of any broader set of relevantly similar cases; indeed, recognition of the idiosyncratic nature of individual cases is central to our argument.

49 McAdam, D., Tarrow, S., and Tilly, C., Dynamics of Contention (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2001), pp. 82–3CrossRefGoogle Scholar.

50 A. Bennett and A. George, ‘Research Design Tasks in Case Study Methods’, Paper presented at MacArthur Foundation Workshop on Case Study Methods, Harvard (October 17–19 1997).

51 Little, A., ‘Feminism and the Politics of Difference in Northern Ireland’, British Journal of Politics and International Relations, 7 (2002), pp. 163–77Google Scholar; Little, A., Democracy and Northern Ireland: Beyond the Liberal Paradigm? (London: Palgrave, 2004)CrossRefGoogle Scholar.

52 Although we focus here on the opportunities that emerged from the domestic context, it is undoubtedly true that the broader international context also made an important contribution. For discussion of the contribution of the Clinton administration see Lynch, T. J., Turf War: The Clinton Administration and Northern Ireland (Aldershot: Ashgate, 2004)Google Scholar. For analysis of the European Union input to the peace process, see Byrne, S. and Irvin, C., ‘Economic aid and policy making: building the peace dividend in Northern Ireland’, Policy and Politics, 29 (2001), pp. 413–29CrossRefGoogle Scholar; O'Dowd, L. and McCall, C., ‘Escaping the Cage of Ethno-National Conflict in Northern Ireland? The Importance of Transnational Networks’, Ethnopolitics, 7 (2008), pp. 8199CrossRefGoogle Scholar; Racioppo, L. and See, K. S., ‘Grassroots Peace-building and Third-party Intervention: The European Union's Special Support Programme for Peace and Reconciliation in Northern Ireland’, Peace and Change, 32 (2007), pp. 361–90CrossRefGoogle Scholar; Williamson, A., Scott, D., and Halfpenny, P., ‘Rebuilding civil society in Northern Ireland: the community and voluntary sector's contribution to the European Union's Peace and Reconciliation District Partnership Programme’, Policy and Politics, 28 (2000), pp. 4966CrossRefGoogle Scholar.

53 Powell, J., Great Hatred, Little Room: Making Peace in Northern Ireland (London: The Bodley Head, 2008)Google Scholar.

54 Dixon, P., ‘Political skills or lying and manipulation? the choreography of the Northern Ireland peace process’, Political Studies, 50 (2002), pp. 725–41CrossRefGoogle Scholar; Dixon, P., The Northern Ireland Peace Process: Choreography and Theatrical Politics (London: Routledge, 2010)Google Scholar.

55 Little, A., Democracy and Northern Ireland: Beyond the Liberal Paradigm? (London: Palgrave, 2004)CrossRefGoogle Scholar; Wider debates on the establishment and nature of consociationalism in Northern Ireland are examined in Taylor, R. (ed.), Consociational Theory (London: Routledge, 2009)Google Scholar; Wilford, R. (ed.), Aspects of the Belfast Agreement (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2010)Google Scholar.

56 Little, A., Democracy and Northern Ireland: Beyond the Liberal Paradigm? (London: Palgrave, 2004)CrossRefGoogle Scholar.

57 Little, A., ‘Disjunctured Narratives: Rethinking Reconciliation and Conflict Transformation’, International Political Science Review, 33:1 (2012) pp. 8298CrossRefGoogle Scholar.

58 G. Gereffi, ‘A Commodity Chains Framework for Analyzing Global Industries’ (1999), available at: {http://www.ids.ac.uk/ids/global/valchn.html}.

59 T. Nagel, ‘The Problem of Global Justice’.

60 Macdonald, K., ‘Global Democracy for a Partially Joined-Up World: Toward a multi-level system of public power and democratic governance?’, in Archibugi, D., Koenig-Archibugi, M., and Marchetti, R. (eds), Global Democracy: Normative and Empirical Perspectives (CambridgeCambridge University Press, 2011)Google Scholar.

61 Haufler, V., A Public Role for the Private Sector: Industry Self-Regulation in a Global Economy (Washington, DC: Carnegie Endowment for International Peace, 2001)Google Scholar; Jenkins, R. O., Corporate codes of conduct: self-regulation in a global economy (Geneva: UNSRID, 2001), pp. ix, 35Google Scholar; Ruggie, J. G., ‘global_governance.net: The Global Compact as Learning Network’, Global Governance, 7 (2001), pp. 371–8Google Scholar.

62 Macdonald, K., ‘Globalising justice within coffee supply chains? Fair Trade, Starbucks and the transformation of supply chain governance’, Third World Quarterly: Special Issue on ‘Beyond CSR? Business, Poverty and Social Justice’, 25 (2007)Google Scholar.

63 Macdonald, K., ‘Global Democracy for a Partially Joined-Up World: Toward a multi-level system of public power and democratic governance?’, in Archibugi, D., Koenig-Archibugi, M., and Marchetti, R. (eds), Global Democracy: Normative and Empirical Perspectives (CambridgeCambridge University Press, 2011)Google Scholar.

64 Connor, T., ‘Re-writing the Rules: The anti-sweatshop movement; Nike, Reebok and Adidas' participation in voluntary labour regulation; and workers' rights to form trade unions and bargain collectively’, Department of Law (Newcastle: University of Newcastle, 2007)Google Scholar.

65 R. Goodin, ‘Global Democracy: In the Beginning’, p. 178.

66 D. Miller, ‘Against Global Democracy’.