Hostname: page-component-8448b6f56d-qsmjn Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-04-23T12:23:32.287Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

DONALD DAVIDSON AND THE ANALYTIC REVOLUTION IN AMERICAN PHILOSOPHY, 1940–1970*

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  05 August 2013

JOEL ISAAC*
Affiliation:
Christ's College, Cambridge
*
Christ's College, Cambridge, CB2 3BUjti20@cam.ac.uk

Abstract

Histories of analytic philosophy in the United States have typically focused on the reception of logical positivism, and especially on responses to the work of the Vienna Circle. Such accounts often call attention to the purportedly positivist-inspired marginalization of normative concerns in American philosophy: according to this story, the overweening positivist concern for logic and physics as paradigms of knowledge displaced questions of value and social relations. This article argues that the reception framework encourages us to mistake the real sources of the analytic revolution in post-war philosophy. These are to be found in debates about intentional action and practical reasoning – debates in which ‘normative’ questions of value and social action were in fact central. Discussion of these topics took place within a transatlantic community of Wittgensteinians, ordinary languages philosophers, logical empiricists, and decision theorists. These different strands of ‘analytical’ thinking were bound together into a new philosophical mainstream not by a positivist alliance with logic and physics, but by the rapid development of the mathematical and behavioural sciences during the Second World War and its immediate aftermath. An illustrative application of this new framework for interpreting the analytic revolution is found in the early career and writings of Donald Davidson.

Type
Articles
Copyright
Copyright © Cambridge University Press 2013 

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

Footnotes

*

This article is based on my 2011 Balzan-Skinner lecture, delivered at the Centre for Research in the Arts, Social Sciences, and Humanities (CRASSH) in the University of Cambridge. I should like to express my gratitude to Mary Jacobus, the director of CRASSH during my tenure there, for helping me settle into a term of research as the 2011 Balzan-Skinner fellow. My thanks also to CRASSH's administrative staff, which carried out the hard work of organizing and promoting the Balzan-Skinner lecture and colloquium. My fellow participants in the colloquium – Thomas Akehurst, Andrew Jewett, Edmund Neill, and Bjørn Ramberg – gave me valuable feedback on the first draft of this article. Finally, I owe special thanks to Quentin Skinner, both for establishing the fellowship I held at CRASSH, and for his suggestions for improvement to the argument presented in the lecture.

References

1 Kuklick, Bruce, A history of philosophy in America, 1720–2000 (Oxford, 2001), pp. 232–7, 243–58Google Scholar; Kloppenberg, James T., ‘Pragmatism: an old name for some new ways of thinking?’, Journal of American History, 83 (1996), pp. 100–38CrossRefGoogle Scholar.

2 Cavell, Stanley, Little did I know (Stanford, CA, 2010), pp. 352–3Google Scholar.

3 Friedman, Michael, Reconsidering logical positivism (Cambridge, 1999)CrossRefGoogle Scholar; Richardson, Alan and Uebel, Thomas, eds., The Cambridge companion to logical empiricism (Cambridge, 2007)CrossRefGoogle Scholar; Hardcastle, Gary L. and Richardson, Alan W., eds., Logical empiricism in North America (Minneapolis, MN, 2003)Google Scholar.

4 Reisch, George R., How the Cold War transformed philosophy of science: to the icy slopes of logic (Cambridge, 2005)CrossRefGoogle Scholar; Howard, Don, ‘Two left turns make a right: on the curious political career of North American philosophy of science at midcentury’, in Hardcastle, and Richardson, , eds., Logical empiricism in North America, pp. 2593Google Scholar.

5 Galison, Peter, ‘The Americanization of unity’, Daedalus, 127 (1998), pp. 4571Google Scholar; Mirowski, Philip, ‘Cyborg agonistes: economics meets operations research in mid-century’, Social Studies of Science, 29 (1999), pp. 685718CrossRefGoogle Scholar; idem, ‘The scientific dimensions of social knowledge and their distant echoes in 20th-century American philosophy of science’, Studies in History and Philosophy of Science: Part A, 35 (2004), pp. 283326CrossRefGoogle Scholar.

6 For two contrasting takes on Davidson's philosophy, see, on the one hand, LePore, Ernest and Ludwig, Kirk, Donald Davidson: meaning, truth, language, and reality (Oxford, 2005)CrossRefGoogle Scholar, and idem, Donald Davidson's truth-theoretic semantics (Oxford, 2007); and, on the other, Malpas, Jeff, ed., Dialogues with Davidson: acting, interpreting, understanding (Cambridge, MA, 2011)CrossRefGoogle Scholar. An accessible introduction to Davidson is provided in Ramberg, Bjørn T., Donald Davidson's philosophy of language: an introduction (Oxford, 1989)Google Scholar. The key collections of essays on Davidson are LePore, Ernest and McLaughlin, Brian P, eds., Actions and events: perspectives on the philosophy of Donald Davidson (Oxford, 1985)Google Scholar; and LePore, Ernest, ed., Truth and interpretation: perspectives on the philosophy of Donald Davidson (Oxford, 1986)Google Scholar.

7 Davidson, , ‘Introduction’, Essays on actions and events (2nd edn, Oxford, 2001), p. xviCrossRefGoogle Scholar.

8 Ibid.

9 Anscombe, Elizabeth, Intention (Oxford, 1957)Google Scholar. See also Moran, Richard, ‘Anscombe on “practical knowledge”’, Royal Institute of Philosophy Supplement, 55 (2004), pp. 4368CrossRefGoogle Scholar.

10 Davidson cites members of each group at the beginning of his essay. See ‘Actions, reasons, and causes’, Journal of Philosophy, 60 (1963), p. 685 n. 1.

11 Davidson identified as the target of his critique of anticausal theories of action ‘most of the books in the series edited by R. F. Holland, Studies in Philosophical Psychology’ and singled out Kenny, Anthony, Action, emotion, and will (London, 1963)Google Scholar, Melden, A. I., Free action (London, 1961)Google Scholar, Winch, Peter, The idea of a social science (London, 1958)Google Scholar, and Peters, R. S., The concept of motivation (London, 1958)Google Scholar. He also specifically addressed Anscombe, Intention.

12 In ‘Actions, reasons, and causes’, Davidson drew on Hampshire, Stuart, Thought and action (London, 1959)Google Scholar, Hart, H. L. A. and Honoré, A. M., Causation in the law (Oxford, 1959)Google Scholar, and Ryle, Gilbert, The concept of mind (New York, NY, 1949)Google Scholar.

13 Davidson cited Dray, William H., Laws and explanation in history (Oxford, 1957)Google Scholar.

14 Hume, David, Enquiries concerning human understanding and concerning the principles of morals, ed. Nidditch, P. H. (1777; Oxford, 1975), pp. 27–8CrossRefGoogle Scholar.

15 Hart and Honoré, Causation, pp. 52–3.

16 See Melden, Free action, pp. 20–1; Ryle, Concept of mind, pp. 80–147.

17 Anscombe, Intention, pp. 69–77; Austin, J. L., ‘A plea for excuses’, Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society, 57 (1956), pp. 130CrossRefGoogle Scholar.

18 Donnellan, Keith, ‘Knowing what I am doing’, Journal of Philosophy, 60 (1963), pp. 401–9CrossRefGoogle Scholar; Hampshire, Stuart and Hart, H. L. A., ‘Decision, intention and certainty’, Mind, 67 (1958), pp. 112CrossRefGoogle Scholar.

19 D'Oro, Giuseppina, ‘Davidson and the autonomy of the human sciences’, in Malpas, , ed., Dialogues with Davidson, pp. 285–6Google Scholar.

20 Davidson, ‘Actions, reasons, and causes’, p. 692.

21 Ibid., p. 691.

22 Ibid., pp. 685–90.

23 In addition to the works by Anscombe, Melden, Hampshire and others cited above, a sign of the renewed interest in the philosophy of action can be found in the Journal of Philosophy's publication of a special issue on the topic in 1963 (before the appearance of ‘Actions, reasons, and causes’). See essays by G. E. M. Anscombe, Richard Brandt and Jaegwon Kim, Arthur Danto, Keith S. Donnellan, Stuart Hampshire, Brian O'Shaughnessy, and Sidney Morgenbesser in Journal of Philosophy, 60, nos. 14 and 15 (1963). See also Chisholm, Roderick M. and Taylor, Richard, ‘Making things to have happened’, Analysis, 20 (1960), pp. 73–8CrossRefGoogle Scholar; Chisholm, Roderick M., ‘The descriptive element in the concept of action’, Journal of Philosophy, 61 (1964), pp. 613–25CrossRefGoogle Scholar.

24 Davidson, ‘Actions’, p. 685.

25 Lepore, Ernest, ‘An interview with Donald Davidson’, in Davidson, , Problems of rationality (Oxford, 2005), pp. 252, 260Google Scholar.

26 Davidson, Donald, ‘Intellectual autobiography’, in Hahn, Lewis Edwin, ed., The philosophy of Donald Davidson (La Salle, IL, 1999), p. 37Google Scholar.

27 Davidson, ‘How is weakness of the will possible?’ (1969), in Essays on action and events, pp. 21–42.

28 The Aristotelian roots of Davidson's theory of action are often neglected in the contemporary commentary on the ‘standard’ Davidsonian account of action. His position is often described as principally Humean in inspiration. See, e.g., Smith, Michael, ‘The structure of orthonomy’, Royal Institute of Philosophy Supplement, 55 (2004), pp. 165–6Google Scholar; idem, ‘The Humean theory of motivation’, Mind, 96 (1987), pp. 36–61; Glüer, Kathrin, Donald Davidson: a short introduction (New York, NY, 2011)CrossRefGoogle Scholar.

29 See Davidson, ‘Aristotle's action’ (2001), in Davidson, Truth, language, and history (Oxford, 2005), pp. 278–80.

30 For Aristotle's account, see Nussbaum, Martha, Aristotle's De Motu Animalium, §7 (Princeton, NJ, 1978)Google Scholar; Aristotle, De Anima, trans. Hugh Lawson-Tancred (London, 1986), pp. 210–16.

31 Anscombe, Intention, pp. 57–66; idem, ‘Thought and action in Aristotle’, in Bamborough, Renford, ed., New essays on Plato and Aristotle (London, 1965), pp. 143–58Google Scholar; Broadie, Alexander, ‘The practical syllogism’, Analysis, 29 (1968), pp. 26–8CrossRefGoogle Scholar; Kenny, A, ‘The practical syllogism and incontinence’, Phronesis, 11 (1966), pp. 163–84CrossRefGoogle Scholar; Mothersill, Mary, ‘Anscombe's account of the practical syllogism’, Philosophical Review, 71 (1962), pp. 448–61CrossRefGoogle Scholar.

32 Davidson, ‘How is weakness of the will possible?’ and ‘Intending’ (1978), in Essays on actions and events. See also Davidson, ‘Aristotle's action’.

33 Davidson, ‘Actions’, p. 697.

34 Davidson, ‘The concept of Aretē and the two lives in the Philebus’ (Honors thesis, Harvard, 1939). Copy in carton 12, Donald Davidson papers, BANC MSS 2005/167, Bancroft Library, University of California at Berkeley (DDP).

35 Davidson, ‘Intellectual autobiography’, p. 22.

36 Official register of Harvard University, 36 (22 Sept. 1939), p. 177; Davidson, ‘Intellectual autobiography’, p. 23.

37 Davidson, ‘Intellectual autobiography’, p. 27.

38 Nash, Gerald, The American West transformed: the impact of the Second World War (Bloomington, IN, 1985)Google Scholar; idem, World War II and the West: reshaping the economy (Lincoln, NE, 1990); Lotchin, Roger W., The bad city in the good war: San Francisco, Los Angeles, Oakland, and San Diego (Bloomington, IN, 2003)Google Scholar; Starr, Kevin, Embattled dreams: California in war and peace, 1940–1950 (New York, NY, 2002)Google Scholar.

39 See Lowen, Rebecca, Creating the Cold War university: the transformation of Stanford (Berkeley, CA, 1997), pp. 6782, 97–102Google Scholar.

40 Ibid., pp. 99–102.

41 Gilmor, C. Stewart, Fred Terman at Stanford: building a discipline, a university, and Silicon Valley (Stanford, CA, 2004), pp. 265–93, 300–47Google Scholar; Lowen, Creating the Cold War university, pp. 103–19.

42 On the ONR and post-war military research agencies, see Shell-Gellasch, Amy, ‘Mina Rees and the funding of the mathematical sciences’, American Mathematical Monthly, 109 (2002), pp. 873–89CrossRefGoogle Scholar; Schweber, S. S., ‘The mutual embrace of science and the military: ONR and the growth of physics in the United States after World War II’, in Mendelsohn, Everett, Smith, Merritt Roe, and Weingart, Peter, eds., Science, technology and the military (Dordrecht, 1988), pp. 345Google Scholar.

43 Gilmor, Fred Terman, pp. 348–419; Lowen, Creating the Cold War university, pp. 147–90.

44 Lécuyer, Christophe, Making Silicon Valley: innovation and the growth of high tech, 1930–1970 (Cambridge, MA, 2005)Google Scholar.

45 Davidson, ‘Intellectual autobiography’, pp. 30–1; Lepore, ‘An interview’, p. 250. See also the teaching materials contained in carton 8, DDP.

46 Davidson, ‘Intellectual autobiography’, p. 30.

47 Lowen, Creating the Cold War university, p. 152.

48 Ford Foundation Grant File 53–82, Ford Foundation Archives, Ford Foundation.

49 Ibid., 30.

50 Davidson, Donald, McKinsey, J. C. C. and Suppes, Patrick, ‘Outlines of a formal theory of value, I’, Philosophy of Science, 22 (1955), pp. 140–60CrossRefGoogle Scholar. A further two parts were slated to appear, but did not appear in the form originally intended, perhaps because of McKinsey's death.

51 Lepore, ‘An interview’, p. 252; Davidson, ‘Intellectual autobiography’, p. 31.

52 Soloman Fefferman and Anita Burdman Fefferman, Alfred Tarski: life and logic (Cambridge, 2005), pp. 160–1, 216.

53 The main concerns of Suppes's work during this period are captured in Patrick Suppes and Muriel Winet, Axiomatization and representation of difference structures, Stanford Value Theory Project, Report No. 2 (Stanford University, Stanford, CA, 29 Mar. 1954); Suppes, Patrick, ‘Some remarks on problems and methods in the philosophy of science’, Philosophy of Science, 21 (1954), pp. 242–8CrossRefGoogle Scholar; Suppes, Patrick and Winet, Muriel, ‘An axiomatization of utility based on the notion of utility differences’, Management Science, 1 (1955), pp. 259–70CrossRefGoogle Scholar.

54 Transcript of interview with Patrick Suppes, Faculty Staff Oral History Project, Stanford University, box 1, SC0932, Stanford University Archives.

55 Lepore, ‘An interview’, p. 261.

56 ‘Philosophy 1964–1965’ and ‘Logic at Stanford’ (promotional materials), papers of the Department of Philosophy, Stanford University, series 3, 4430, Stanford University Archives.

57 Vickrey, William, ‘Measuring marginal utility by reactions to risk’, Econometrica, 13 (1945), pp. 319–33CrossRefGoogle Scholar; Friedman, Milton and Savage, L. J., ‘The utility analysis of choices involving risk’, Journal of Political Economy, 56 (1948), pp. 279304CrossRefGoogle Scholar; Marschak, Jacob, ‘Rational behavior, uncertain prospects, and measurable utility’, Econometrica, 18 (1950), pp. 111–41CrossRefGoogle Scholar; Arrow, Kenneth J., ‘Alternative approaches to the theory of choice in risk-taking situations’, Econometrica, 19 (1951), pp. 404–37CrossRefGoogle Scholar; Savage, L. J., ‘The theory of statistical decision’, Journal of the American Statistical Association, 46 (1951), pp. 5567CrossRefGoogle Scholar; Mosteller, Frederick and Nogee, Philip, ‘An experimental measurement of utility’, Journal of Political Economy, 59 (1951), pp. 371404CrossRefGoogle Scholar.

58 For one of Davidson's expositions of this problem, see Davidson, Donald, ‘Belief and the basis of meaning’, Synthese, 27 (1974), pp. 309–23CrossRefGoogle Scholar.

59 Ramsey, Frank Plumpton, ‘Truth and probability’ (1926), in Braithwaite, R. B., ed., The foundations of mathematics and other logical essays (London, 1931), pp. 156–98Google Scholar.

60 Davidson, Donald and Suppes, Patrick, ‘A finitistic axiomatization of subjective probability and utility’, Econometrica, 24 (1956), pp. 264–75CrossRefGoogle Scholar; Davidson, Donald and Marschak, Jacob, ‘Experimental tests of the stochastic decision theory’, in Churchman, C. West and Ratoosh, Philburn, eds., Measurement: definitions and theories (New York, NY, 1959), pp. 233–69Google Scholar. See also Suppes and Winet, Axiomatization and representation; Donald Davidson and Patrick Suppes, Finitistic rational choice structures, Stanford Value Theory Project, Report No. 3 (Stanford University, Stanford, CA, 4 Mar. 1955); Davidson, Donald, Siegel, Sidney and Patrick Suppes, , Some experiments and related theory on the measurement of utility and subjective probability, Stanford Value Theory Project, Report No. 4 (Stanford University, Stanford, CA, 15 Aug. 1955)Google Scholar.

61 Davidson, Donald and Suppes, Patrick, with Sidney Siegel, Decision making: an experimental approach (Stanford, CA, 1957)Google Scholar.

62 See, most explicitly, Davidson, Donald, ‘A new basis for decision theory’, Theory and Decision, 18 (1985), pp. 8798CrossRefGoogle Scholar.

63 International Congress for Logic, Methodology, and Philosophy of Science: Abstracts of Contributed Papers (Stanford University, Stanford, CA, 24 Aug. – 2 Sept. 1960), Folder – box 4440–2: Logic, Papers of the Department of Philosophy, Stanford University, Stanford University Archives.

64 Morgenbesser to Donald Davidson, 15 May 1963, carton 3, DDP.

65 A point urged in Davidson, ‘A unified theory of thought, meaning, and action’, in Problems of rationality, pp. 151–66.

66 Feigl, Herbert, ‘The logical character of the principle of induction’, Philosophy of Science, 1 (1934), pp. 20–9CrossRefGoogle Scholar; Reichenbach, Hans, ‘Induction and probability’, Philosophy of Science, 3 (1936), pp. 124–6CrossRefGoogle Scholar; Carnap, Rudolf, ‘Testability and meaning’, Philosophy of Science, 3 (1936), pp. 419–71CrossRefGoogle Scholar; idem, ‘Testability and meaning – continued’, Philosophy of Science, 4 (1937), pp. 140CrossRefGoogle Scholar; Reichenbach, Hans, ‘On the justification of induction’, Journal of Philosophy, 37 (1940), pp. 97103CrossRefGoogle Scholar.

67 Rau, Erik P., ‘The adoption of Operations Research in the United States during World War II’, in Hughes, Thomas P. and Hughes, Agatha C., eds., Systems, experts, and computers: the systems approach in management and engineering, World War II and after (Cambridge, MA, 2000), pp. 5792CrossRefGoogle Scholar; Rau, Erik P., ‘Technological systems, expertise, and policy making: the British origins of operational research’, in Allen, Michael Thad and Hecht, Gabrielle, eds., Technologies of power: essays in honor of Thomas Parke Hughes and Agatha Chipley Hughes (Cambridge, MA, 2001), pp. 215–52Google Scholar; Thomas, William, ‘The heuristics of war: scientific method and the founders of operations research’, British Journal for the History of Science, 40 (2007), pp. 251–74CrossRefGoogle Scholar.

68 Rees, Mina, ‘The mathematical sciences and World War II’, American Mathematical Monthly 87 (1980), p. 611CrossRefGoogle Scholar.

69 Ibid.; Shell-Gellasch, ‘Mina Rees’, p. 878; Mirowski, ‘Cyborg agonistes’, pp. 699–703.

70 See, e.g., Friedman and Savage, ‘Utility analysis’; Savage, ‘Theory’; Friedman, Milton and Savage, L. J., ‘The expected-utility hypothesis and the measurability of utility’, Journal of Political Economy, 60 (1952), pp. 463–74CrossRefGoogle Scholar; Savage, L. J. et al. , ‘On the foundations of statistical inference: discussion’, Journal of the American Statistical Association, 57 (1962), pp. 307–26CrossRefGoogle Scholar.

71 Fortun, M. and Schweber, S. S., ‘Scientists and the legacy of World War II: the case of operations research (OR)’, Social Studies of Science, 23 (1993), pp. 595642CrossRefGoogle Scholar; Waring, Stephen P., ‘Cold calculus: the Cold War and Operations Research’, Radical History Review, 63 (1995), pp. 2951CrossRefGoogle Scholar; Mirowski, ‘Cyborg agonistes’; Rau, ‘Adoption’; Shell-Gellasch, ‘Mina Rees’; Thomas, ‘Heuristics’.

72 Mirowski, ‘Cyborg agonistes’, p. 705; Mirowski, ‘Scientific dimensions’, pp. 309–10; Quine, W. V., The time of my life (Cambridge, MA, 1985), p. 217Google Scholar.

73 Churchman, C. West and Ackoff, Russell L., ‘Varieties of unification’, Philosophy of Science, 13 (1946), pp. 287300CrossRefGoogle Scholar; Ackoff, Russell L., ‘An educational program for the philosophy of science’, Philosophy of Science, 16 (1949), pp. 154–7CrossRefGoogle Scholar; Suppes, ‘Some remarks’.

74 See, e.g., the references in nn. 57 and 70.

75 Perry, Ralph Barton, ‘The definition of value’, Journal of Philosophy, Psychology and Scientific Methods, 11 (1914), pp. 141–62CrossRefGoogle Scholar; idem, ‘Economic value and moral value’, Quarterly Journal of Economics, 30 (1916), pp. 443–85CrossRefGoogle Scholar; idem, ‘Value as election and satisfaction’, International Journal of Ethics, 41 (1931), pp. 429–42CrossRefGoogle Scholar; Dewey, John, Theory of valuation (Chicago, IL, 1939)Google Scholar; idem, ‘Valuation judgments and immediate quality’, Journal of Philosophy, 40 (1943), pp. 309–17CrossRefGoogle Scholar; idem, ‘Some questions about value’, Journal of Philosophy, 41 (1944), pp. 449–55CrossRefGoogle Scholar; Lewis, Clarence Irving, An analysis of knowledge and valuation (La Salle, IL, 1947)Google Scholar; Mosteller and Nogee, ‘Experimental measurement’.

76 See the notes in folder marked ‘2/61: ‘Outlines of a formal theory of value’, carton 2, DDP.

77 See folder marked ‘2/62: ‘Outlines of a formal theory of value (seminar)’, carton 2, DDP.

78 Donald Davidson, fellowship application to the Fund for the Advancement of Education, c. 1952, carton 2, DDP.

79 Davidson, fellowship application to the ACLS, 14 Oct. 1957, carton 2, DDP.