Hostname: page-component-8448b6f56d-jr42d Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-04-17T20:18:44.777Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

FOLK RETRIBUTIVISM AND THE COMMUNICATION CONFOUND

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  11 July 2013

Thomas Nadelhoffer
Affiliation:
College of Charleston, USA
Saeideh Heshmati
Affiliation:
University of Arizona, USA
Deanna Kaplan
Affiliation:
University of Arizona, USA
Shaun Nichols
Affiliation:
University of Arizona, USAshaunbnichols@gmail.com

Abstract

Retributivist accounts of punishment maintain that it is right to punish wrongdoers, even if the punishment has no future benefits. Research in experimental economics indicates that people are willing to pay to punish defectors. A complementary line of work in social psychology suggests that people think that it is right to punish wrongdoers. This work suggests that people are retributivists about punishment. However, all of the extant work contains an important potential confound. The target of the punishment is expected to be aware of the punitive act. Thus, it's possible that people punish because they want to communicate something to the wrongdoer, e.g. disapproval, the presence of a norm, etc. In three studies, we examine whether people will punish even when the punishee will be ignorant. We find that people are no less likely to punish when the punishee will be ignorant. This finding emerges both in a survey study and in a monetized behavioural decision study.

Type
Articles
Copyright
Copyright © Cambridge University Press 2013 

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

References

REFERENCES

Andreoni, J. and Vesterlund, L.. 2001. Which is the fair sex? Gender differences in altruism. Quarterly Journal of Economics 116: 293312.Google Scholar
Braithwaite, J. and Pettit, P.. 1990. Not Just Deserts. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Buhrmester, M., Kwang, T. and Gosling, S.. 2011. Amazon's Mechanical Turk: a new source of inexpensive, yet high-quality, data? Psychological Science 6: 35.Google Scholar
Carlsmith, K. M. 2006. The roles of retribution and utility in determining punishment. Journal of Experimental Social Psychology 42: 437451.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Carlsmith, K. M. 2008. On justifying punishment: The discrepancy between words and actions. Social Justice Research 21: 119137.Google Scholar
Carlsmith, K. M. and Darley, J. M.. 2008. Psychological aspects of retributive justice. Advances in Experimental Social Psychology 40: 193236. San Diego, CA: Elsevier.Google Scholar
Carlsmith, K. M., Darley, J. M. and Robinson, P. H.. 2002. Why do we punish? Deterrence and just deserts as motives for punishment. Journal of Personality and Social Psychology 83: 284299.Google Scholar
Cottingham, J. G. 1979. Varieties of retributivism. Philosophical Quarterly 29: 238246.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Dana, J., Dave, C. and Friedman, E.. (forthcoming). Nosy preferences and welfare destruction in the laboratory. University of Pennsylvania.Google Scholar
Darley, J. M., Carlsmith, K. M. and Robinson, P. H.. 2000. Incapacitation and just deserts as motives for punishment. Law and Human Behavior, 24, 659683.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Davis, M. H. 1980. A multidimensional approach to individual differences in empathy. JSAS Catalog of Selected Documents in Psychology 10: 85.Google Scholar
Davis, M. H. 1983. Measuring individual differences in empathy: evidence for a multidimensional approach. Journal of Personality and Social Psychology 44: 113126.Google Scholar
Duff, R. A. 2001. Punishment, Communication, and Community. New York: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Duff, R. A. and Garland, D.. 1994. Introduction: Thinking about punishment. In A Reader on Punishment, ed. Duff, R. A. & Garlan, D., 143. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Dufwenberg, M. and Muren, A.. 2006. Gender composition in teams. Journal of Economic Behavior and Organization 61: 5054.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Fehr, E. and Gächter, S.. 2002. Altruistic punishment in humans. Nature 415: 137140.Google Scholar
Fehr, E. and Gachter, S.. 2005. Human behaviour: Egalitarian motive and altruistic punishment (reply). Nature 433: E1E2.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Fehr, E. and Fischbacher, U. 2004. Third party punishment and social norms. Evolution and Human Behavior 25: 6387.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Feinberg, J. 1965. The expressive function of punishment. The Monist 49: 397423.Google Scholar
Fowler, J., Johnson, T. and Smirnov, O.. 2005. Egalitarian motive and altruistic punishment. Nature 433: E1.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Gollwitzer, M. and Denzler, M.. 2009. What makes revenge so sweet: seeing the offender suffer or delivering a message? Journal of Experimental Social Psychology 45: 840844.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Hermann, B., Thoni, C. and Gachter, S.. 2008. Antisocial punishment across societies. Science 319: 13621367.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Hoffman, E., McCabe, K., Shachat, K. and Smith, V. L.. 1994. Preferences, property rights and anonymity in bargaining games. Games and Economic Behavior 7: 346380.Google Scholar
Hogarth, J. 1971. Sentencing as a Human Process. Toronto: University of Toronto Press.Google Scholar
Kahneman, D., Schkade, D. and Sunstein, C. R.. 1998. Shared outrage and erratic awards: the psychology of punitive damages. Journal of Risk and Uncertainty 16: 4986.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Lacey, N. 1988. State Punishment: Political Principles and Community Values. London: Routledge.Google Scholar
McFatter, R. M. 1978. Sentencing strategies and justice: effects of punishment philosophy on sentencing decisions. Journal of Personality and Social Psychology 36: 14901500.Google Scholar
McFatter, R. M. 1982. Purposes of punishment: effects of utilities of criminal sanctions on perceived appropriateness. Journal of Applied Psychology 67: 255267.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Mill, J. S. 1979 [1861]. Utilitarianism. Indianapolis, IN: Hackett Publishing.Google Scholar
Monroe, A. E. and Malle, B. F.. 2010. From uncaused will to conscious choice: the need to study, not speculate about, people's folk concept of free will. Review of Philosophy and Psychology 1: 34.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Moore, M. 1997. Placing Blame: A General Theory of the Criminal Law. Oxford: Clarendon Press.Google Scholar
Nadelhoffer, T., Nahmias, E. and Sripada, C.. (in prep). The Free Will Inventory: Measuring beliefs about free will.Google Scholar
Nahmias, E., Morris, S., Nadelhoffer, T. and Turner, J.. 2006. Is incompatibilism intuitive? Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 73: 2853.Google Scholar
Nichols, S. 2007. After incompatibilism: a naturalistic defense of the reactive attitudes. Philosophical Perspectives 21: 405428.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Nichols, S. and Knobe, J.. 2007. Moral responsibility and determinism: the cognitive science of folk intuitions. Nous 41: 663685.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Pratto, F., Sidanius, J., Stallworth, L. M. and Malle, B. F.. 1994. Social dominance orientation: a personality variable predicting social and political attitudes. Journal of Personality and Social Psychology 67: 741763.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Shariff, A. F., Greene, J. D. and Schooler, J. W.. (in prep). His brain made him do it: encouraging a mechanistic worldview reduces punishment.Google Scholar
Sidgwick, H. 1874. Methods of Ethics. London: Macmillan.Google Scholar
Sommers, T. 2012. Relative Justice: Cultural Diversity, Free Will, and Moral Responsibility. Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press.Google Scholar
Vidmar, N. 1974. Retributive and utilitarian motives and other correlates of Canadian attitudes toward the death penalty. Canadian Psychologist 15: 337356.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Vohs, K. and Schooler, J.. 2008. The value of believing in free will: encouraging a belief in determinism increases cheating. Psychological Science 19: 4954.Google Scholar
Von Hirsch, A. 1993. Censure and Sanctions. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Zizzo, D. and Oswald, A.. 2001. Are people willing to pay to reduce others’ incomes? Annales D’économie et de statistique 63–64: 3965.Google Scholar
Supplementary material: PDF

Nadelhoffer et al. supplementary material

Supplementary material

Download Nadelhoffer et al. supplementary material(PDF)
PDF 115.5 KB