Hostname: page-component-7c8c6479df-5xszh Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-03-29T15:26:14.730Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

Exploitation and Rational Choice

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  25 November 2011

Loren King*
Affiliation:
Wilfrid Laurier University
*
Loren King, Department of Political Science, Wilfrid Laurier University, 75 University Avenue West, Waterloo, Ontario, CanadaN2L 3C5, lking@wlu.ca

Abstract

Abstract. Critics fault rational choice theory for dubious assumptions and limited explanatory power. The aims of rational choice are, however, as much normative as explanatory, and I argue that an abiding concern of political thought—the wrong of exploitation—gives moral weight to some of the more substantive assumptions underlying many rational choice prescriptions.

Résumé. Les critiques reprochent à la théorie du choix rationnel d'avancer des hypothèses douteuses et d'offrir des explications restreintes. Les objectifs du choix rationnel sont, cependant, aussi bien normatifs qu'explicatifs. J'affirme qu'une préoccupation centrale de la pensée politique – le mal de l'exploitation – donne une signification morale à certains postulats du choix rationnel.

Type
Research Article
Copyright
Copyright © Canadian Political Science Association 2011

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

References

Allais, Maurice. 1953. “Rational Man's Behavior in the Presence of Risk: Critique of the Postulates and Axioms of the American School.” Econometrica 21: 503–46.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Anand, Paul. 1993. Foundations of Rational Choice under Risk. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Andreou, Chrisoula. 2006. “Environmental Damage and the Puzzle of the Self-Torturer.” Philosophy and Public Affairs 34: 95108.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Arrow, Kenneth J. 1951. Social Choice and Individual Valuess. 2nd ed.New Haven CT: Yale University Press, 1963.Google Scholar
Austen-Smith, David and Banks, Jeffrey. 1988. “Elections, Coalitions, and Legislative Outcomes.” American Political Science Review 82: 405–22.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Axelrod, Robert. 1986. “An Evolutionary Approach to Norms.” American Political Science Review 80: 10951111.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Bardsley, Nicholas. 2008. “Dictator Game Giving: Altruism or Artifact?Experimental Economics 11: 122–33.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Baron, David P. and Ferejohn, John A.. 1989. “Bargaining in Legislatures.” American Political Science Review 83: 11811206.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Bates, Robert H., Greif, Avner, Levi, Margaret, Rosenthal, Jean-Laurent and Weingast, Barry R.. 1998. Analytic Narratives. Princeton NJ: Princeton University Press.Google Scholar
Bendor, Jonathan, Diermeier, Daniel and Ting, Michael. 2003. “A Behavioral Model of Turnout.” American Political Science Review 97: 261–80.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Bernoulli, Daniel. 1954 [1738]. “Exposition of a New Theory on the Measurement of Risk,” trans. Summer, Louise. Econometrica 22: 2336.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Binmore, Ken. 1998. Just Playing: Game Theory and the Social Contract, vol. II. Cambridge MA: MIT Press.Google Scholar
Binmore, Ken. 2009. Rational Decisions. Princeton NJ: Princeton University Press.Google Scholar
Binmore, Ken and Voorhoeve, Alex. 2003. “Defending Transitivity against Zeno's Paradox.” Philosophy and Public Affairs 31: 272–79.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Binmore, Ken and Shaked, Avner. 2010. “Experimental Economics: Where Next?Journal of Economic Behavior and Organization 73: 87100.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Black, Duncan. 1958. Theory of Committees and Elections. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Brams, Steven J., Davis, Morton D. and Straffin, Philip D. Jr. 1979. “The Geometry of the Arms Race.” International Studies Quarterly 23: 567–88.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Bratman, Michael E. 1987. Intention, Plans, and Practical Reason. Cambridge MA: Harvard University Press.Google Scholar
Buchanan, Allen. 1990. “Justice as Reciprocity versus Subject-Centered Justice.” Philosophy & Public Affairs 19: 227–52.Google Scholar
Chong, Dennis. 2000. Rational Lives: Norms and Values in Politics and Society. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Christiano, Thomas. 2004. “Is Normative Rational Choice Theory Self-Defeating?Ethics 115: 122–41.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Cubitt, Robin P. and Sugden, Robert. 2001. “On Money Pumps.” Games and Economic Behavior 37: 121–60.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Downs, Anthony. 1957. An Economic Theory of Democracy. New York: Harper.Google Scholar
Eckel, Catherine and Gintis, Herbert. 2010. “Blaming the Messenger: Notes on the Current State of Experimental Economics.” Journal of Economic Behavior & Organization 73: 109–19.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Ellsberg, Daniel. 1961. “Risk, Ambiguity, and the Savage Axioms.” Quarterly Journal of Economics 75: 643–69.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Elster, Jon. 1979. Ulysses and the Sirens: Studies in Rationality and Irrationality. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Fessler, Daniel M.T. 2009. “Return of the Lost Letter: Experimental Framing Does Not Enhance Altruism in an Everyday Context.” Journal of Economic Behavior & Organization 71: 575–78.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Fishburn, Peter C. 1983. “Ellsberg Revisited: A New Look at Comparative Probability.” Annals of Statistics 11: 1047–59.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Fishburn, Peter C. and Wakker, Peter. 1995. “The Invention of the Independence Condition for Preferences.” Management Science 41: 1130–44.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Frankfurt, Harry G. 1971. “Freedom of the Will and the Concept of a Person.” Journal of Philosophy 68: 520CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Franssen, Maarten. 1994. “Constrained Maximization Reconsidered: An Elaboration and Critique of Gauthier's Modelling of Rational Choice in a Single Prisoners' Dilemma.” Synthese 101: 249–72.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Frohlich, Norman and Oppenheimer, Joe. 2006. “Skating on Thin Ice: Cracks in the Public Choice Foundation.” Journal of Theoretical Politics 18 (3): 235–66.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Gauthier, David. 1969. The Logic of Leviathan: the Moral and Political Theory of Thomas Hobbes. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Gauthier, David. 1986. Morals by Agreement. Oxford: Clarendon.Google Scholar
Gauthier, David. 1997. “Resolute Choice and Rational Deliberation: a Critique and Defense.” Nous 31: 135.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Geertz, Clifford. 1972. “Deep Play: Notes on the Balinese Cockfight.” Daedalus 101: 137.Google Scholar
Geertz, Clifford. 1973. “Thick Description: Toward and Interpretive Theory of Culture.” In The Interpretation of Cultures. New York: Basic Books.Google Scholar
Gintis, Herbert. 2000. “Strong Reciprocity and Human Sociality.” Journal of Theoretical Biology 206: 169–79.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Gintis, Herbert. 2009. The Bounds of Reason: Game Theory and the Unification of the Behavioral Sciences. Princeton NJ: Princeton University Press.Google Scholar
Gintis, Herbert and Bowles, Samuel, Boyd, Robert and Fehr, Ernst. 2003. “Explaining Altruistic Behavior in Humans.” Evolution and Human Behavior 24: 153–72.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Green, Donald and Shapiro, Ian. 1994. Pathologies of Rational Choice Theory. New Haven: Yale University Press.Google Scholar
Hacking, Ian. 1983. Representing and Intervening: Introductory Topics in the Philosophy of Natural Science. New York: Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Hardin, Russell. 2001. “The Normative Core of Rational Choice Theory.” In The Economic World View: Studies in the Ontology of Economics, ed. Maki, Uskali. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Hausman, Daniel M. 1995. “Rational Choice and Social Theory: A Comment.” Journal of Philosophy 92: 96102.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Henrich, Joseph. 2000. “Does Culture Matter in Economic Behavior? Ultimatum Game Bargaining among the Machiguenga of the Peruvian Amazon.” American Economic Review 90: 973–79.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Henrich, Joseph, McElreath, Richard, Barr, Abigail, Ensminger, Jean, Barrett, Clark, Bolyanatz, Alexander, Cardenas, Juan Camilo, Gurven, Michael, Gwako, Edwins, Henrich, Natalie, Lesorogol, Carolyn, Marlowe, Frank, Tracer, David and Ziker, John. 2006. “Costly Punishment across Human Societies.” Science 312: 1767–70.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Henrich, Joseph, McElreath, Richard, Barr, Abigail, Ensminger, Jean, Barrett, Clark, Bolyanatz, Alexander, Cardenas, Juan Camilo, Gurven, Michael, Gwako, Edwins, Henrich, Natalie, Lesorogol, Carolyn, Marlowe, Frank, Tracer, David and Ziker, John. 2010. “Markets, Religion, Community Size, and the Evolution of Fairness and Punishment.” Science 327: 1480–84.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Houghton, David. 1995. “Reasonable Doubts about Rational Choice.” Philosophy 70: 5368.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Jackman, Simon and Sniderman, Paul M.. 2006. “The Limits of Deliberative Discussion: a Model of Everyday Political Arguments.” Journal of Politics 68: 272–83.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Jervis, Robert J. 1988. “Realism, Game Theory, and Cooperation.” World Politics 40: 317–49.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Johnson, James. 2006. “Consequences of Positivism: a Pragmatist Assessment.” Comparative Political Studies 39: 224–52.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Johnson, James. 2010. “What Rationality Assumption? Or, How ‘Positive Political Theory’ Rests on a Mistake.” Political Studies 58: 282–99.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Jones, Bryan D. 2001. Politics and the Architecture of Choice: Bounded Rationality and Governance. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.Google Scholar
Joyce, James. 1999. Foundations of Causal Decision Theory. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Keller, Evelyn Fox. 2000. “Models of and Models for: Theory and Practice in Contemporary Biology.” Philosophy of Science 67: S72S86.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Knight, Frank. 1921. Risk, Uncertainty, and Profit. Boston: Houghton Mifflin.Google Scholar
Korsgaard, Christine M. 1996. The Sources of Normativity. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Kydd, Andrew. 1997. “Game Theory and the Spiral Model.” World Politics 49: 371400.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Laibson, David and Yariv, Leeat. 2007. “Safety in Markets: an Impossibility Theorem for Dutch Books.” Manuscript, http://www.economics.harvard.edu/faculty/laibson/files/LaibsonYariv.pd (September 7, 2010).Google Scholar
Lane, Ruth. 1996. “Positivism, Scientific Realism, and Political Science.” Journal of Theoretical Politics 8: 361–82CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Lee, Richard. 1984. “Preference and Transitivity.” Analysis 44: 129–34.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Levitt, Steven D. and List, John A.. 2007. “What Do Laboratory Experiments Measuring Social Preferences Reveal about the Real World?Journal of Economic Perspectives 21: 153–74.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Loomes, Graham, Starmer, Chris and Sugden, Robert. 1991. “Observing Violations of Transitivity by Experimental Methods.” Econometrica 59: 425–39.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Machina, Mark J. 1982. “‘Expected Utility’ Analysis without the Independence Axiom.” Econometrica 50: 277323.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Mackie, Gerry. 2003. Democracy Defended. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Maher, Patrick. 1993. Betting on Theories. New York: Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
McClennen, Edward F. 1990. Rationality and Dynamic Choice: Foundational Explorations. New York: Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
McDermott, Rose. 2004. “The Feeling of Rationality: the Meaning of Neuroscientific Advances for Political Science.” Perspectives on Politics 2: 691706.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
McKelvey, Richard D. and Palfrey, Thomas R.. 1995. “Quantal Response Equilibria for Normal Form Games.” Games and Economic Behavior 10: 638.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
McKelvey, Richard D. and Palfrey, Thomas R. 1998. “Quantal Response Equilibria for Extensive Form Games.” Experimental Economics 1: 638.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Mutz, Diana. 2006. Hearing the Other Side: Deliberative versus Participatory Democracy. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Myerson, Roger B. 1991. Game Theory: Analysis of Conflict. Cambridge MA: Harvard University Press.Google Scholar
Narveson, Jan. 2010. “The Relevanc eof Decision Theory to Ethical Theory.” Ethical Theory and Moral Practice 13: 497520.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Ostrom, Elinor. 1998. “A Behavioral Approach to the Rational Choice Theory of Collective Action.” American Political Science Review 92: 122.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Ostrom, Elinor. 2000. “Collective Action and the Evolution of Fairness Norms.” Journal of Economic Perspectives 14: 137–58.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Ostrom, Elinor. 2006. “The Value-Added of Laboratory Experiments for the Study of Institutions and Common-Pool Resources.” Journal of Economic Behavior and Organization 61: 149–63.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Pettit, Philip. 1997. Republicanism: a Theory of Freedom and Government. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Philips, Michael. 1989. “Must Rational Preferences be Transitive?Philosophical Quarterly 39: 477–83.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Popkin, Samuel L. 1979. The Rational Peasant: the Political Economy of Rural Society in Vietnam. New Haven: Yale University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Quinn, Warren S. 1990. “The Puzzle of the Self-Torturer.” Philosophical Studies 59: 7990.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Rachels, Stuart. 1998. “Counterexamples to the Transitivity of Better Than.” Australasian Journal of Philosophy 76: 7183.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Rawls, John. 1999 [1971]. A Theory of Justice. 2nd ed.Cambridge MA: Belnap Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Raz, Joseph. 1975. Practical Reason and Norms. London: Hutchinson.Google Scholar
Riker, William H. 1980. “Implications from the Disequilibrium of Majority Rule for the Study of Institutions.” American Political Science Review 74: 432–46.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Rubinstein, Ariel and Spiegler, Ran. 2008. “Money Pumps in the Market.” Journal of the European Economic Association 6: 237–53.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Samuelson, Paul A. 1952. “Probability, Utility, and the Independence Axiom.” Econometrica 20: 670–78.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Satz, Debra and Ferejohn, John. 1994. “Rational Choice and Social Theory.” Journal of Philosophy 91: 7187.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Savage, Leonard J. 1954. Foundations of Statistics. New York: Wiley.Google Scholar
Scott, James C. 1976. The Moral Economy of the Peasant: Rebellion and Subsistence in Southeast Asia. New Haven: Yale University Press.Google Scholar
Scott, James C. 1985. Weapons of the Weak: Everyday Forms of Peasant Resistance. New Haven: Yale University Press.Google Scholar
Sen, Amartya K. 1985. “Rationality and Uncertainty.” In Rationality and Freedom. Cambridge MA: Harvard Belknap.Google Scholar
Shapiro, Ian. 2005. The Flight from Reality in the Human Sciences. Princeton NJ: Princeton University Press.Google Scholar
Signorino, Curtis S. 1999. “Strategic Interaction and the Statistical Analysis of International Conflict.” American Political Science Review 93: 279–97.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Simon, Herbert A. 1955. “A Behavioral Model of Rational Choice.” Quarterly Journal of Economics 69: 99118.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Simon, Herbert A. 1985. “Human Nature in Politics: the Dialogue of Psychology with Political Science.” American Political Science Review 79: 293304.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Skyrms, Brian. 1996. Evolution of the Social Contract. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Skyrms, Brian. 2004. The Stag Hunt and the Evolution of Social Structure. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Sugden, Robert. 1985. “Why Be Consistent? A Critical Analysis of Consistency Requirements in Choice Theory.” Economica 52: 167–83.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Taylor, Charles. 1971. “Interpretation and the Sciences of Man.” Review of Metaphysics 25: 351.Google Scholar
Taylor, Charles. 1977. “What is Human Agency?” In Human Agency and Language: Philosophical Papers, vol. I. New York: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Taylor, Charles. 1982. “Rationality.” In Rationality and Relativism, ed. Hollis, Martin and Lukes, Steven. Cambridge MA: MIT Press.Google Scholar
Temkin, Larry. 1996. “A Continuum Argument for Intransitivity.” Philosophy and Public Affairs 25: 175210.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Tricomi, Elizabeth, Rangel, Antonio, Camerer, Colin F. and O'Doherty, John P.. 2010. “Neural Evidence for Inequality-Averse Social Preferences.” Nature 463: 1089–91.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Tversky, Amos and Kahneman, Daniel. 1979. “Prospect Theory: An Examination of Decision under Risk.” Econometrica 47: 263291.Google Scholar
Tversky, Amos and Kahneman, Daniel. 1981. “The Framing of Decisions and the Psychology of Choice.” Science 211: 453–58.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Uzan-Milofsky, Marie. 2009. “Shall We Be Resolute?Rationality and Society 21: 337–57.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Voorhoeve, Alex. 2008. “Heuristics and Biases in a Purported Counter-example to the Acyclicity of ‘Better Than.’Politics, Philosophy & Economics 7: 285–99.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Weber, Michael. 1998. “The Resilience of the Allais Paradox.” Ethics 109: 94118.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Woodward, James. 2008. “Social Preferences in Experimental Economics.” Philosophy of Science 75: 646–57.CrossRefGoogle Scholar