Hostname: page-component-76fb5796d-vvkck Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-04-25T11:18:10.595Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

Epistemic Identities

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  03 January 2012

Abstract

This paper explores the significant strengths of Fricker's account, and then develops the following questions. Can volitional epistemic practice correct for non-volitional prejudices? How can we address the structural causes of credibility-deflation? Are the motivations behind identity prejudice mostly other-directed or self-directed? And does Fricker aim for neutrality vis-à-vis identity, in which case her account conflicts with standpoint theory?

Type
Research Article
Copyright
Copyright © Cambridge University Press 2010

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

References

REFERENCES

Alcof, L. M. 2007. “Epistemologies of Ignorance: Three Types.” In Tuana, N. and Sullivan, S. (eds.), Race and Epistemologies of Ignorance, pp. 3957. Albany, NY: SUNY Press.Google Scholar
Amodio, D.M. 2008. “The Social Neuroscience of Intergroup Relations.” European Review of Social Psychology 19: 154.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Fricker, M. 2007. Epistemic Injustice: Power and the Ethics of Knowing. Oxford: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Gladwell, M. 2005. Blink: The Power of Thinking without Thinking. New York: Little, Brown and Co. Google Scholar
Harding, S. 1986. The Science Question in Feminism. Ithaca, NY: Cornell University Press.Google Scholar
Harding, S. (ed.) 2004. The Feminist Standpoint Theory Reader. New York: Routledge.Google Scholar
Haslanger, S. 2008. “Changing the Ideology and Culture of Philosophy: Not by Reason (Alone).” Hypatia 23(2): 210–23.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Hirschfeld, L. A. 1996. Race in the Making: Cognition, Culture, and the Child's Construction of Human Kinds. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.Google Scholar
LeDoeu, M. 1989. The Philosophical Imaginary. Gordon, C. (trans.). Stanford: Stanford University Press.Google Scholar
LeDoeuff, M. 2007. Hipparchia's Choice: An Essay Concerning Women, Philosophy, Etc. T., Selous (trans.). New York: Columbia University Press.Google Scholar
MacDonald, K. 20062007. “Psychology and White Ethnocentrism.” The Occidental Quarterly 6(4): 746.Google Scholar
Steele, C. M. 1997. “A Threat in the Air: How Stereotypes Shape the Intellectual Identities and Performance of Women and African-Americans.” American Psychologist 52: 613–29.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Steele, C. M. and Aronson, J.. 1995. “Stereotype Threat and the Intellectual Test Performance of African-Americans.” Journal of Personality and Social Psychology 69: 797811.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Trawalter, S. and Richeson, J. A.. 2006. “Regulatory Focus and Executive Function After Interracial Interactions.” Journal of Experimental Social Psychology 42: 406–12.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Trawalter, S., Todd, A., Baird, A. A., and Richeson, J. A.. 2008. “Attending to Threat: Race-based Patterns of Selective Attention.” Journal of Experimental Social Psychology 44: 1322–27.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed