Hostname: page-component-8448b6f56d-wq2xx Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-04-24T19:42:25.368Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

Economic Epistemology: Hopes and Horrors

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  03 January 2012

Extract

The cultural and epistemic status of science is under attack. Social and cultural studies of science are widely perceived to offer evidence and arguments in support of an anti-science campaign. They portray science as a mundane social endeavour, akin to religion and politics, with no privileged access to truthful information about the (socially unconstructed) real world. Science is under threat and needs defence. Old philosophical legitimations have lost their bite. Alarm bells ring, new troops have to be mobilised. Call economics, the good old friend of the status quo depicting it as a generally beneficial social order while accommodating a rather mundane picture of human behaviour. In contrast to constructivist and relativist sociology of scientific knowledge, economic accounts of science seek to provide a rigorous defence of the cultural and epistemic legitimacy of science by accommodating plausible elements in the sociological accounts and by embedding them in invisible-hand arguments about the functioning of some market-like structure within science. Viewed through economic spectacles, science re-emerges from the ashes as stronger and more beautiful than ever. A spectator raises an innocent question: is economics itself strong and beautiful enough to offer such alleviating services? In order to examine the emerging issue of disciplinary credibility, we need to look at economics itself more closely, and we need to address traditional issues in the philosophy of science as well as less traditional issues of reflexivity. We will see that the above caricature concerning the role of economics in the science wars calls for heavy qualifications if not wholesale rejection (no comment here on the caricatured role of the SSK).

Type
Research Article
Copyright
Copyright © Cambridge University Press 2005

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

References

Arthur, Brian W. (1994) Increasing Returns and Path Dependence in the Economy. Ann Arbor: University of Michigan Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Bannerjee, A.V. (1992) “A simple model of herd behaviorQuarterly Journal of Economics, 107, 797817.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
IIIBartley, W.W. (1990) Unfathomed Knowledge, Unmeasured Wealth. La Salle: Open Court.Google Scholar
Bikhchandani, Sushil, Hirshleifer, David, & Welch, Ivo (1992) “A theory of fads, fashion, custom, and cultural change as informational cascadesJournal of Political Economy, 100, 9921026.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Buchanan, James (1999) Has Economics Lost Its Way? Fairfax: Institute for Humane Studies.Google Scholar
Colander, David (1991) Why Aren't Economists as Important as Garbagemen? Armonk: M.E. Sharpe.Google Scholar
David, Paul (1985) “Clio and the economics of QWERTYAmerican Economic Review, Proceedings, 75, 332337.Google Scholar
Frank, Robert H., Gilovich, Thomas D., & Regan, Dennis T. (1993) “Doe studying economics inhibit cooperation?” Journal of Economic Perspectives, 7, 159171.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Goldman, Alvin I. (1999) Knowledge in a Social World. Oxford: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Goldman, Alvin I. & Shaked, M. (1991) “An economic model of scientific activity and truth acquisitionPhilosophical Studies, 63, 3155.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Hands, Wade D. (1995) “Social epistemology meets the invisible hand: Kitcher on the advancement of scienceDialogue, 34, 605621.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Hands, Wade D. (1997) “Caveat emptor: Economics and contemporary philosophy of science”, Philosophy of Science, 64, S107–S116.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Hands, Wade D. (2001) Reflection without Rules. Economic Methodology and Contemporary Science Theory. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Hull, David L. (1988) Science as a Process. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Kitcher, Philip (1993) “The division of cognitive labor”, Journal of Philosophy, 87, 522.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Kitcher, Philip (1993) The Advancement of Science. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Luetge, Christoph (2004) “Economics in philosophy of science: A dismal contribution?”, Synthese, 140, 279305.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Mäki, Uskali (1993) “Social theories of science and the fate of institutionalism in economics” in Rationality, Institutions and Economic Methodology, edited by Mäki, Uskali, Gustafsson, Bo & Knudsen, Christian. London: Routledge. Pp. 76109.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Mäki, Uskali (1999) “Science as a free market: A reflexivity test in an economics of economics”, Perspectives on Science, 7, 486509.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Mäki, Uskali (1999) “The dismal queen of the social sciences”, in Fact and Fiction in Economics. Realism, Models, and Social Construction, ed. Mäki, U.. Cambridge University Press. Pp. 334.Google Scholar
Mäki, Uskali (2005) “Models are experiments, experiments are models”, Journal of Economic Methodology, 12 (2)CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Mayer, Thomas (1993) Truth and Precision in Economics. Aldershot: Edward Elgar.Google Scholar
Mirowski, Philip (1996) “The economic consequences of Philip KitcherSocial Epistemology, 10, 153169.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Mirowski, Philip (1997) “On playing the economics trump card in the philosophy of science: Why did it not work for Michael PolanyiPhilosophy of Science, 64, S127–S138.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Reder, Melvin W. (1999) Economics: The Culture of a Controversial Science. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.Google Scholar
Rescher, Nicholas (1989) Cognitive Economy: The Economic Dimension of the Theory of Knowledge. Pittsburgh: University of Pittsburgh Press.Google Scholar
Rescher, Nicholas (1996) Priceless Knowledge? Natural Science in Economic Perspective. Lanham: Rowman & Littlefield.Google Scholar
Roorda, Jonathan (1997) “Kitcher on theory choiceErkenntnis, 46, 215239.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Rubinstein, Ariel (2004) “Dilemmas of an economic theorist”, unpublished Presidential Address to the Econometric Society.Google Scholar
Sent, Esther-Mirjam (1997) “An economist's glance at Goldman's economicsPhilosophy of Science, 64, S139–S148.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Strevens, Michael (2003) “The role of the priority rule in scienceJournal of Philosophy, 100, 5579.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Sugden, Robert (2002) “Credible worlds. The status of theoretical models in economics”, in Fact and Fiction in Economics: Models, Realism, and Social Construction, edited by Mäki, Uskali. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. Pp. 107136CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Ylikoski, Pteri (1995) “The invisible hand and scienceScience Studies 8 (2), 3243.Google Scholar
Zamora, Jesus Bonilla (1999) “The elementary economics of scientific consensusTheoria 14, 461488.Google Scholar
Zamora, Jesus Bonilla (2002a) “Scientific inference and the pursuit of fame: A contractarian approachPhilosophy of Science, 69, 300323.Google Scholar
Zamora, Jesus Bonilla (2002b) “Economists: Truth-seekers or rent-seekers”, in Fact and Fiction in Economics: Models, Realism, and Social Construction. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. Pp. 356375.Google Scholar