Hostname: page-component-8448b6f56d-jr42d Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-04-19T03:15:19.129Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

Minding One's Cognitive Systems: When Does a Group of Minds Constitute a Single Cognitive Unit?

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  03 January 2012

Extract

The possibility of group minds or group mental states has been considered by a number of authors addressing issues in social epistemology and related areas (Goldman 2004, Pettit 2003, Gilbert 2004, Hutchins 1995). An appeal to group minds might, in the end, do indispensable explanatory work in the social or cognitive sciences. I am skeptical, though, and this essay lays out some of the reasons for my skepticism. The concerns raised herein constitute challenges to the advocates of group minds (or group mental states), challenges that might be overcome as theoretical and empirical work proceeds. Nevertheless, these hurdles are, I think, genuine and substantive, so much so that my tentative conclusion will not be optimistic. If a group mind is supposed to be a single mental system having two or more minds as proper parts, the prospects for group minds seem dim–or so I will argue.

Type
Research Article
Copyright
Copyright © Cambridge University Press 2005

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

References

Adams, F. & Aizawa, K. (2001). “The Bounds of Cognition.” Philosophical Psychology 14: 4364.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Block, Ned (1986). “Advertisement for a Semantics for Psychology.” In French, P.Uehling, T., and Wettstein, H. (eds.), Midwest Studies in Philosophy, Vol. 10: Studies in the Philosophy of Mind (Minneapolis: University of Minnesota Press), pp. 615–78.Google Scholar
Chalmers, D. (1996). The Conscious Mind: In Search of a Fundamental Theory. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Chalmers, D. (2002). “Consciousness and Its Place in Nature.” In Chalmers, D. (ed.), Philosophy of Mind: Classical and Contemporary Readings (Oxford: Oxford University Press), pp. 247–72.Google Scholar
Cummins, R. (1996). Representations, Targets, and Attitudes. London: MIT Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Dretske, F. (1988). Explaining Behavior: Reasons in a World of Causes. London: MIT Press.Google Scholar
Fodor, J. (1983). The Modularity of Mind. London: MIT Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Fodor, J. (1987). Psychosemantics: The Problem of Meaning in the Philosophy of Mind. London: MIT Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Fodor, J. (1990). A Theory of Content and Other Essays. London: MIT Press.Google Scholar
Fodor, J. (1994). The Elm and the Expert: Mentalese and Its Semantics. London: MIT Press.Google Scholar
Fodor, J. (2000). The Mind Doesn't Work That Way: The Scope and Limits of Computational Psychology. London: MIT Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Fodor, J. & LePore, E. (1992). Holism: A Shopper's Guide. Oxford: Blackwell.Google Scholar
Gilbert, M. (2004). “Collective Epistemology.” EPISTEME 1: 0-17 (pagination refers to typescript).CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Goldman, A. (2004). “Group Knowledge Versus Group Rationality: Two Approaches to Social Epistemology,” EPISTEME 1: 1122.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Grush, R. (1997) “The Architecture of Representation.” Philosophical Psychology 10: 523.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Hutchins, E. (1995). Cognition in the Wild. London: MIT Press.Google Scholar
Maloney, J. C. (1994). “Content: Covariation, Control, and Contingency.” Synthese 100: 241–90.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Millikan, R. (1984) Language, Thought, and Other Biological Categories: New Foundations for Realism. London: MIT Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Pettit, P. (2003) “Groups with Minds of Their Own,” in Schmitt, F. (ed.), Socializing Metaphysics, Oxford: Rowman and Littlefield.Google Scholar
Prinz, J. (2002). Furnishing the Mind: Concepts and Their Perceptual Basis. London: MIT Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Putnam, H. (1975). Mind, Language, and Reality: Philosophical Papers, Volume 2. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Rupert, R. (1998). “On the Relationship between Naturalistic Semantics and Individuation Criteria for Terms in a Language of Thought.” Synthese 117: 95131.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Rupert, R. (1999). “The Best Test Theory of Extension: First Principle(s).” Mind and Language 14 (1999): 321355.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Rupert, R. (2001). “Coining Terms in the Language of Thought: Innateness, Emergence, and the Lot of Cummins's Argument against the Causal Theory of Mental Content.” The Journal nof Philosophy 98: 499530.Google Scholar
Schlosser, G. (1998) “Self-reproduction and Functionality: A Systems-Theoretical Approach to Teleological Explanation.” Synthese 116: 303354.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Segal, G. (2002) A Slim Book about Narrow Content. London: MIT Press.Google Scholar
Slater, C. (1994). “Discrimination without Indication: Why Dretske Can't Lean on Learning.” Mind and Language 9: 163–80.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Velleman, J. D. (1997) “How to Share an Intention,” Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 57: 2950.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Wilson, R. (2004) Boundaries of the Mind: The Individual in the Fragile Sciences. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar