Hostname: page-component-8448b6f56d-c47g7 Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-04-24T12:28:39.725Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

Remembering Alston's ‘evaluative particularism’

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  12 July 2010

DEAN A. KOWALSKI*
Affiliation:
UW-Waukesha, 1500 N. University Ave, Waukesha, WI 53188

Abstract

William Alston uniquely offers the divine-command theorist his ‘evaluative particularism’ – the idea that God Himself, the concrete individual, uniquely serves as the supreme standard of (moral) goodness. This allegedly retains God's sovereignty over the moral realm without subverting His goodness or entailing that there are moral principles, the truth of which does not depend on God. However, it is argued that Alston's view faces three initial challenges: justificatory analogies with the two most viable particularist programmes fail; disanalogies between scientific and scriptural data jeopardize the prospect of determining God's relevant essential properties a posteriori; and it harbours problematic entailments regarding (human) moral goodness even if the first two challenges are met.

Type
Articles
Copyright
Copyright © Cambridge University Press 2010

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

References

Alston, William (1991) ‘Some suggestions for divine command theorists’, in Beaty, Michael(ed.) Christian Theism and the Problems of Philosophy (Notre Dame IN: Notre Dame University Press), 303326.Google Scholar
Alston, William (2002) ‘What Euthyphro should have said’, in Lane Craig, William(ed.) Philosophy of Religion (New Brunswick NJ: Rutgers University Press), 283298.Google Scholar
Alston, William (2005) ‘Response to Zagzebski’, in Battaly, Heather & Lynch, Michael (eds) Perspectives on the Philosophy of William P. Alston (Lanham MD: Rowman & Littlefield), 203207.Google Scholar
Craig, William Lane (2008) ‘Opening statement and rebuttals’, in Garcia, Robert K. & King, Nathan L. (eds) Is Goodness without God Good Enough? (Lanham MD: Rowman & Littlefield).Google Scholar
Craig, William Lane & Walter, Sinnott-Armstrong (2004) God? (New York NY: Oxford University Press).Google Scholar
Ehrman, Bart D. (2005) Misquoting Jesus: The Story Behind Who Changed the Bible and Why (New York NY: HarperCollins).Google Scholar
Fales, Evan (1996) ‘Scientific explanations of mystical experience, part I: The case of St Teresa’, Religious Studies, 32, 143–63.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Fales, Evan (1996a) ‘Scientific explanations of mystical experience, part II: The challenge to theism’, Religious Studies, 32, 297313.Google Scholar
Hasker, William, et al. (1994) The Openness of God (Downers Grove IL: InterVarsity Press).Google Scholar
Kripke, Saul (1980) Naming and Necessity (Oxford: Blackwell).Google Scholar
Morriston, Wes (2001) ‘A standard of moral goodness apart from God?,’ Philosophia Christi, 3, 127138.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Zagzebski, Linda (2005) ‘More suggestions for divine command theorists’, in Battaly, & Lynch, Perspectives on the Philosophy of William P. Alston.Google Scholar