Hostname: page-component-8448b6f56d-tj2md Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-04-19T03:34:26.469Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

Deliberation, Democracy, and the Rule of Reason in Aristotle's Politics

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  28 April 2011

JAMES LINDLEY WILSON*
Affiliation:
Princeton University
*
James Lindley Wilson is a Ph.D. candidate, Department of Politics, Princeton University, 130 Corwin Hall, Princeton, NJ 08544-1012 (jlw@princeton.edu).

Abstract

Deliberative democratic theorists argue that important moral questions turn on whether regimes are sufficiently deliberative. To attribute “deliberativeness” to a regime, we need an account of “deliberative integration” that connects such a holistic assessment to the acts or qualities of individuals and smaller groups. I turn to Aristotle's Politics for instruction in developing such accounts, arguing that he judges regimes according to how reliably they act pursuant to excellent common deliberation—a manner of excellent rule that I call the “rule of reason.” I then interpret Aristotle's metaphorical argument for the “wisdom of the multitude” to establish the claim that democracies may best integrate citizens’ deliberations. This interpretation illuminates Aristotle's complex evaluation of regimes, including his ambivalent views on the rule of the many. It also suggests a structure for contemporary accounts of deliberative integration helpful even for those who differ from Aristotle in their basic moral concerns.

Type
Research Article
Copyright
Copyright © American Political Science Association 2011

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

References

REFERENCES

Aristotle, . [1962] 1999. Nichomachean Ethics. Trans. Ostwald, Martin. Upper Saddle River, NJ: Prentice Hall.Google Scholar
Aristotle, . 1982. Aristotle's Poetics. Trans. Hutton, James. New York: W.W. Norton.Google Scholar
Aristotle, . 1984. The Politics. Trans. Lord, Carnes. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Aristotle, . 1984. The Rhetoric and Poetics of Aristotle. Trans. Roberts, W. Rhys and Bywater, Ingram (respectively). New York: Random House.Google Scholar
Athenaeus, . 2006. The Learned Banqueters, Volume I. Trans. Olson, S. Douglas. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.Google Scholar
Athenaeus, . 2009. The Learned Banqueters, Volume V. Trans. Olson, S. Douglas. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.Google Scholar
Audi, Robert. 1995. “Acting from Virtue.Mind 104 (415): 449–71.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Bickford, Susan. 1996. The Dissonance of Democracy: Listening, Conflict, and Citizenship. Ithaca, NY: Cornell University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Blickman, Daniel R. 1987. “Styx and the Justice of Zeus in Hesiod's ‘Theogony.’Phoenix 41 (4): 341–55.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Buchanan, Allen. 2004. Justice, Legitimacy, and Self-determination: Moral Foundations for International Law. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Chambers, Simone. 2009. “Rhetoric and the Public Sphere: Has Deliberative Democracy Abandoned Mass Democracy?Political Theory 37 (3): 323–50.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Clay, Jenny Strauss. 1993. “The Generation of Monsters in Hesiod.” Classical Philology 88 (2): 105–16.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Coby, Patrick. 1988. “Aristotle's Three Cities and the Problem of Faction.” Journal of Politics 50 (4): 896919.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Cohen, Joshua. 1989. “Deliberation and Democratic Legitimacy.” In The Good Polity: Normative Analysis of the State, eds. Hamlin, Alan and Pettit, Philip. Oxford: Basil Blackwell, 1734.Google Scholar
Dobbs, Darrell. 1996. “Family Matters: Aristotle's Appreciation of Women and the Plural Structure of Society.” American Political Science Review 90 (1): 7489.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Dryzek, John S. 2001. “Legitimacy and Economy in Deliberative Democracy.” Political Theory 29 (5): 651–69.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Estlund, David. 2008. Democratic Authority. Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press.Google Scholar
Frank, Jill. 1998. “Democracy and Distribution: Aristotle on Just Desert.” Political Theory 26 (6): 784802.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Frank, Jill. 2005. A Democracy of Distinction: Aristotle and the Work of Politics. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.Google Scholar
Goodin, Robert E., and Dryzek, John S.. 2006. “Deliberative Impacts: The Macro-political Uptake of Mini-publics.” Politics and Society 34 (2): 219–44.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Gottlieb, Paula. 1994. “Aristotle on Dividing the Soul and Uniting the Virtues.” Phronesis 39 (3): 275–90.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Gutmann, Amy, and Thompson, Dennis. 2004. Why Deliberative Democracy? Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Habermas, Jürgen. 1987. The Theory of Communicative Action, Vol. 2: Lifeworld and System: A Critique of Functionalist Reason. Trans. McCarthy, Thomas. Boston: Beacon.Google Scholar
Habermas, Jürgen. 1990. “Discourse Ethics: Notes on a Program of Philosophical Justification.” In Moral Consciousness and Communicative Action. Trans. Lenhardt, Christian and Nicholson, Shierry Weber. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press, 43115.Google Scholar
Habermas, Jürgen. 1996. Between Facts and Norms. Trans. Rehg, William. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Habermas, Jürgen. 2006. “Political Communication in Media Society: Does Democracy Still Enjoy an Epistemic Dimension? The Impact of Normative Theory on Empirical Research.” Communication Theory 16 (4): 411–26.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Hendriks, Carolyn M. 2006. “Integrated Deliberation: Reconciling Civil Society's Dual Role in Deliberative Democracy.” Political Studies 54 (3): 486508.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Herodotus, . 2007. The Landmark Herodotus: The Histories, ed. Strassler, Robert B.. New York: Pantheon Books.Google Scholar
Hesiod, . 2006. Hesiod: Theogony, Works and Days, Testimonia. Trans. Most, Glenn W.. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.Google Scholar
Homer, . 1919. The Odyssey, Volume 1. Trans. Murray, A.T.. London: William Heinemann.Google Scholar
Jaffa, Harry. 1963. “Aristotle.” In History of Political Philosophy, eds. Strauss, Leo and Cropsey, Joseph. Chicago: Rand McNally, 64129.Google Scholar
Keyt, David. 1991. “Aristotle's Theory of Distributive Justice.” In A Companion to Aristotle's Politics, eds. Keyt, David and Miller, Fred D. Jr. Cambridge, MA: Blackwell, 238–78.Google Scholar
Kirby, John T. 1997. “Aristotle on Metaphor.” American Journal of Philology 118 (4): 517–54.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Kraut, Richard. 2002. Aristotle: Political Philosophy. Oxford: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Levy, Harold. 1990. “Does Aristotle Exclude Women from Politics?Review of Politics 52 (3): 397416.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Lindsay, Thomas. 1992a. “Aristotle's Qualified Defense of Democracy through ‘Political Mixing.’Journal of Politics 54 (1): 101–19.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Lindsay, Thomas K. 1992b. “Liberty, Equality, Power: Aristotle's Critique of the Democratic ‘Presupposition.’American Journal of Political Science 36 (3): 743–61.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Manin, Bernard. 1997. The Principles of Representative Government. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Mara, Gerald M. 1998. “Interrogating the Identities of Excellence: Liberal Education and Democratic Culture in Aristotle's Nichomachean Ethics.” Polity 31 (2): 301–29.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Mondi, Robert. 1986. “Tradition and Innovation in the Hesiodic Titanomachy.” Transactions of the American Philological Association 116: 2548.Google Scholar
Mulgan, R.G. 1977. Aristotle's Political Theory. New York: Clarendon Press.Google Scholar
Newell, W.R. 1987. “Superlative Virtue: The Problem of Monarchy in Aristotle's ‘Politics.’Western Political Quarterly 40 (1): 159–78.Google Scholar
Nichols, Mary P. 1992. Citizens and Statesmen: A Study of Aristotle's Politics. Savage, MD: Rowman and Littlefield.Google Scholar
Ober, Josiah. 1998. Political Dissent in Democratic Athens: Intellectual Critics of Popular Rule. Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press.Google Scholar
Ober, Josiah. 2008. Democracy and Knowledge: Innovation and Learning in Classical Athens. Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Rawls, John. 1999. A Theory of Justice. rev. ed. Cambridge, MA: Belknap.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Salkever, Stephen G. 1990. Finding the Mean: Theory and Practice in Aristotelian Political Philosophy. Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press.Google Scholar
Salkever, Stephen G. 2002. “The Deliberative Model of Democracy and Aristotle's Ethic of Natural Questions.” In Aristotle and Modern Politics, ed. Tessitore, Aristide. Notre Dame, IN: University of Notre Dame Press, 342–74.Google Scholar
Theophrastus, . 1993. Characters. Trans. Rusten, Jeffrey. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.Google Scholar
Thompson, Dennis F. 2008. “Deliberative Democratic Theory and Empirical Political Science.” Annual Review of Political Science 11: 497520.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Waldron, Jeremy. 1995. “The Wisdom of the Multitude: Some Reflections on Book 3, Chapter 11 of Aristotle's Politics.” Political Theory 23 (4): 563–84.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Winthrop, Delba. 1978. “Aristotle on Participatory Democracy.” Polity 11 (2): 151–71.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Yack, Bernard. 1993. The Problems of a Political Animal. Berkeley: University of California Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Yack, Bernard. 2006. “Rhetoric and Public Reasoning: An Aristotelian Understanding of Political Deliberation.” Political Theory 34 (4): 417–38.CrossRefGoogle Scholar