Hostname: page-component-8448b6f56d-42gr6 Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-04-20T00:39:43.526Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

Two problems with “self-deception”: No “self” and no “deception”

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  03 February 2011

Robert Kurzban
Affiliation:
Department of Psychology, University of Pennsylvania, Philadelphia, PA 19104. kurzban@psych.upenn.eduhttp://www.psych.upenn.edu/~kurzban/

Abstract

While the idea that being wrong can be strategically advantageous in the context of social strategy is sound, the idea that there is a “self” to be deceived might not be. The modular view of the mind finesses this difficulty and is useful – perhaps necessary – for discussing the phenomena currently grouped under the term “self-deception.”

Type
Open Peer Commentary
Copyright
Copyright © Cambridge University Press 2011

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

References

Barrett, H. C. (2005) Enzymatic computation and cognitive modularity. Mind and Language 20:259–87.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Barrett, H. C. & Kurzban, R. (2006) Modularity in cognition: Framing the debate. Psychological Review 113:628–47.Google Scholar
Churchland, P. (1987) Epistemology in the age of neuroscience. Journal of Philosophy 84:544–53.Google Scholar
Dawkins, R. & Krebs, J. (1978) Animal signals: Information or manipulation? In: Behavioural ecology: An evolutionary approach, ed. Krebs, J. & Davies, N., pp. 282309. Blackwell Scientific.Google Scholar
Dennett, D. (1981) Brainstorms: Philosophical essays on mind and psychology. MIT Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Fodor, J. (1983) The modularity of mind. MIT Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Fodor, J. (2000) The mind doesn't work that way. Bradford Books/MIT.Google Scholar
Humphrey, N. & Dennett, D. C. (1998) Speaking for our selves. In: Brainchildren: Essays on designing minds, ed. Dennet, D. C., pp. 3158. Penguin Books.Google Scholar
Kurzban, R. (in press) Why everyone (else) is a hypocrite: Evolution and the modular mind. Princeton University Press.Google Scholar
Kurzban, R. & Aktipis, C. A. (2006) Modular minds, multiple motives. In: Evolution and social psychology, ed. Schaller, M., Simpson, J. & Kenrick, D., pp. 3953. Psychology Press.Google Scholar
Kurzban, R. & Aktipis, C. A. (2007) Modularity and the social mind: Are psychologists too self-ish? Personality and Social Psychology Review 11:131–49.Google Scholar
Kurzban, R. & Christner, J. (in press) Are supernatural beliefs commitment devices for intergroup conflict? In: The psychology of social conflict and aggression (The Sydney Symposium of Social Psychology, vol. 13), ed. Forgas, J. P., Kruglanski, A. & Willimas, K. D..Google Scholar
McKay, R. T. & Dennett, D. C. (2009) The evolution of misbelief. Behavioral and Brain Sciences 32(6):493561.Google Scholar
Pears, D. (1985) The goals and strategies of self-deception. In: The multiple self, ed. Elster, J., pp. 5977. Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Pinker, S. (1997) How the mind works. Norton.Google Scholar
Rorty, A. O. (1985) Self-deception, akrasia and irrationality. In: The multiple self, ed. Elster, J., pp. 115–32. Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Stich, S. (1983) From folk psychology to cognitive science: The case against belief. Bradford.Google Scholar
Taylor, S. E. (1989) Positive illusions: Creative self-deception and the healthy mind. Basic Books.Google Scholar
Tooby, J. & Cosmides, L. (1992) The psychological foundations of culture. In: The adapted mind: Evolutionary psychology and the generation of culture, ed. Barkow, J. H., Cosmides, L. & Tooby, J., pp. 19136. Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Wegner, D. M. (2005) Who is the controller of controlled processes? In: The new unconscious, ed. Hassin, R., Uleman, J. S. & Bargh, J. A., pp. 1936. Oxford University Press.Google Scholar