Hostname: page-component-8448b6f56d-t5pn6 Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-04-18T02:16:32.848Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

Communication and the representation of thought: The use of audience-directed expressions in free indirect thought representations1

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  14 December 2009

DIANE BLAKEMORE*
Affiliation:
University of Salford
*
Author's address: School of Languages, University of Salford, Salford, Greater Manchester M5 4WT, UKD.Blakemore@salford.ac.uk

Abstract

This paper examines the use of audience-directed or inherently communicative expressions (discourse markers and interjections) in free indirect thought representations in fiction. It argues that the insights of Banfield's (1982) no-narrator approach to free indirect style can be accommodated in a relevance theoretic framework. The result is an account in which the author's act of revealing a character's thoughts communicates a guarantee of optimal relevance – a guarantee which justifies the effort which the reader invests in deriving meta-representations of those thoughts from the evidence which the author provides. However, the reward for this effort is a meta-representation of a character's thoughts which is unmediated by the thoughts of the author who is responsible for producing the text. Using examples from fiction, I show that within this framework, the use of procedurally encoded discourse markers and interjections contribute to this sense of immediacy by imposing constraints on interpretation which leave the reader with the responsibility for deriving his own interpretations of a character's thoughts and thought processes.

Type
Research Article
Copyright
Copyright © Cambridge University Press 2009

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

Footnotes

[1]

I am extremely grateful to Nigel Fabb and two anonymous JL referees for comments on earlier versions of this paper. Obviously, they are not to be held responsible for any of the arguments it contains.

References

REFERENCES

Bach, Kent. 1999. The myth of conventional implicature. Linguistics and Philosophy 22, 327366.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Banfield, Anne. 1982. Unspeakable sentences: Narration and representation in the language of fiction. London: Routledge & Kegan Paul.Google Scholar
Banfield, Anne. 2005. ‘No-narrator’ theory. In Herman, David, Jahn, Manfred & Ryan, Marie-Laure (eds.), The Routledge encyclopaedia of Narrative Theory, 396397. London: Routledge.Google Scholar
Blakemore, Diane. 1987. Semantic constraints on relevance. Oxford: Blackwell.Google Scholar
Blakemore, Diane. 2002. Relevance and linguistic meaning: The semantics and pragmatics of discourse markers. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Blakemore, Diane. 2008. Apposition and affective communication. Language and Literature 17.1, 3758.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Blass, Regina. 1989. Grammaticalization of interpretive use: The case of ‘re’ in Sissala. Lingua 79, 229236.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Blass, Regina. 1990. Relevance relations in discourse: A study with special reference to Sissala. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Bronzwaer, W. J. M. 1970. Tense in the novel. Groningen: Wolters-Noordhoff.Google Scholar
Carston, Robyn. 2002. Thoughts and utterances. Oxford: Blackwell.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Chatman, Seymour. 1978. Story and discourse: Narrative structure in fiction and film. Ithaca, NY: Cornell University Press.Google Scholar
Conrad, Joseph. 1963. The secret agent. Harmondsworth: Penguin Books. [First published 1907]Google Scholar
Dickens, Charles. 1979. Our mutual friend. Harmondsworth: Penguin Books. [First published 1860]Google Scholar
Dickens, Charles. 1978. Little Dorrit. Harmondsworth: Penguin Books. [First published 1857]Google Scholar
Dillon, George & Kirchhoff, Frederick. 1976. On the form and function of free indirect style. PTL: A Journal for Descriptive Poetics and Theory of Literature 1, 431440.Google Scholar
Ehrlich, Susan. 1990. Point of view: A linguistic analysis of literary style. London: Routledge.Google Scholar
Fludernik, Monika. 1993. The fictions of language and the languages of fiction. London: Routledge.Google Scholar
Grace, Patricia. 2001. Dogside story. Harmondsworth: Penguin Books.Google Scholar
Hall, Alison. 2007. Do discourse markers encode concepts or procedures? Lingua 111.1, 149174.Google Scholar
Ifantidou-Trouki, Elly. 1993. Sentence adverbials and relevance. Lingua 90, 6990.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Jucker, Andreas H. 1993. The discourse marker well: A relevance-theoretic account. Journal of Pragmatics 19, 435452.Google Scholar
Kaplan, David. 1997. What is meaning? Ms., University of California, Los Angeles.Google Scholar
Lowry, Malcolm. 1962. Under the volcano. Harmondsworth: Penguin Books. [First published by Jonathan Cape, 1947]Google Scholar
Mansfield, Katherine. 1981. The collected short stories. Harmondsworth: Penguin Books.Google Scholar
Pilkington, Adrian. 2000. Poetic thoughts and poetic effects: A relevance theory perspective. Amsterdam: John Benjamins.Google Scholar
Potts, Christopher. 2005. The logic of conventional implicatures. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Potts, Christopher. 2007. The expressive dimension. Theoretical Linguistics 33.2, 165197.Google Scholar
Quirk, Randolph, Greenbaum, Sidney, Leech, Geoffrey & Svartvik, Jan. 1985. A comprehensive grammar of the English language. London: Longman.Google Scholar
Reinhart, Tanya. 1983. Points of view in language – the use of parentheticals. In Rauh, Gisa (ed.), Essays on deixis, 169194. Tübingen: Gunter Narr.Google Scholar
Rieber, Stephen. 1997. Conventional implicatures as tacit performatives. Linguistics and Philosophy 20, 5172.Google Scholar
Schlenker, Philippe. 2004. Context of thought and context of utterance: A note on free indirect discourse and the historical present. Mind & Language 19.1, 279304.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Sharvit, Yael. 2008. The puzzle of free indirect discourse. Linguistics and Philosophy 31.3, 353395.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Sperber, Dan & Wilson, Deirdre. 1995. Relevance: Communication and cognition (2nd edn.). Oxford: Blackwell. [First published 1986]Google Scholar
Sternberg, Meir. 1982. Point of view and indirections of direct speech. Language and Style 15.1, 67–117.Google Scholar
Tannen, Deborah. 1989. Talking voices: Repetition, dialogue and imagery in conversational discourse (Studies in Interactional Sociolinguistics 6). Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Wharton, Tim. 2003a. Natural pragmatics and natural codes. Mind & Language 18, 447477.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Wharton, Tim. 2003b. Interjections, language and the ‘showing–saying’ continuum. Pragmatics & Cognition 11, 3991.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Wilson, Deirdre. 2000. Metarepresentation in linguistic communication. In Sperber, Dan (ed.), Metarepresentation: A multi-disciplinary perspective, 411448. Oxford: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Wilson, Deirdre. 2006. The pragmatics of irony: Echo or pretence. Lingua 116, 17221743.Google Scholar
Wilson, Deirdre & Sperber, Dan. 1993. Linguistic form and relevance. Lingua 90.1/2, 125.Google Scholar
Wilson, Deirdre & Wharton, Tim. 2006. Relevance and prosody. Journal of Pragmatics 38, 15591579.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Woolf, Virginia. 1964. To the lighthouse. Harmondsworth: Penguin Books. [First published by the Hogarth Press, 1925]Google Scholar