Hostname: page-component-8448b6f56d-m8qmq Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-04-18T02:45:38.151Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

The Intelligibility of the Universe

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  04 May 2010

Extract

Hume famously warned us that the ‘[The] ultimate springs and principles are totally shut up from human curiosity and enquiry’. Or, again, Newton: ‘Hitherto I have not been able to discover the cause of these properties of gravity … and I frame no hypotheses.’ Aristotelian science was concerned with just such questions, the specification of occult qualities, the real essences that answer the question What is matter, etc?, the preoccupation with circular definitions such as dormative virtues, and so on. The rise of modern science is usually seen as a break with the sterility of Aristotelianism, so what exactly is it that modern science does discover, if it is not the essential nature of matter, of force, of energy, of space and time? A famous answer was provided by Poincaré: ‘The true relations between these real objects are the only reality we can attain.’ This is often regarded as the manifesto of so-called structural realism, as espoused in recent years by John Worrall, for example (cp. his (1989)). In response to the arguments of Larry Laudan (1982) against convergent realism, Worrall points to the continuity in the formal relations between elements of reality expressed by mathematical equations, while the intrinsic nature of these elements of reality gets constantly revised.

Type
Papers
Copyright
Copyright © The Royal Institute of Philosophy and the contributors 2001

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

References

Carnap, R. (1929) Der Logisches Aufbau der Welt (Berlin: Schlachtensee Weltbreis-Verlag).Google Scholar
Caws, P. (1988) Structuralism: The Art of the Intelligible (New Jersey and London: Humanities Press International).Google Scholar
Chakravartty, A. (1998) ‘Semirealism’, Studies in History and Philosophy of Science, 29, 391408.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Connes, A. (1990) Géométrie Non-Commutative, (Paris: Inter Editions).Google Scholar
Demopoulos, W. and Friedman, M. (1985) ‘Critical Notice: Bertrand Russell's The Analysis of Matter: Its Historical Context and Contemporary Interest’, Philosophy of Science, 52, 621–39.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Duhem, P. (1906) La Théorie Physique: Son Objet, Sa Structure (Paris: Chevalier et Rivière).Google Scholar
Dummett, M. (1991) Frege: Philosophy of Mathematics (Cambridge, Mass.: Harvard University Press).Google Scholar
English, J. (1973) ‘Underdetermination: Craig and Ramsey’, Journal of Philosophy, 70, 453–62.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Goldstein, J. (1980) Classical Mechanics, 2nd edition, (Reading, Mass: Addison Wesley).Google Scholar
Hume, D. (1777) An Enquiry concerning Human Understanding, posthumous edition, Selby-Bigge edition (1902), (Oxford: Clarendon Press).Google Scholar
Jones, R. (1991) ‘Realism about What?’, Philosophy of Science, 58, 185202.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Ladyman, J. (1998) ‘What is Structural Realism?’, Studies in History and Philosophy of Science, 29, 409–24.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Laudan, L. (1982) ‘A Confutation of Convergent Realism’, Philosophy of Science, 48, 1949.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Maxwell, G. (1970a) ‘Structural Realism and the Meaning of Theoretical Terms’, in Winokur, S. and Radner, M. (eds) Analyses of Theories, and Methods of Physics and Psychology (Minneapolis: University of Minnesota Press), pp. 181–92.Google Scholar
Maxwell, G. (1970b) ‘Theories, Perception and Structural Realism’ in Colodny, R. (ed.) Nature and Function of Scientific Theories, (Pittsburgh: University of Pittsburgh Press), pp. 334.Google Scholar
Poincaré, H. (1902) La Science et l'Hypothése (Paris: Flammarion, English translation (1952) New York: Dover).Google Scholar
Newton, I. (1713) Philosophiae Naturalis Principia Mathematica 2nd edition, The 1929 Motte translation edited by Florian Cajori (1934), (Berkeley and Los Angeles: University of California Press).Google Scholar
Post, H. R. (1971) ‘Correspondence, Invariance and Heuristics: In Praise of Conservative Induction’, Studies in History and Philosophy of Science, 2, 213–55.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Newman, M. H. A. (1928) ‘Mr. Russell's Causal Theory of Perception’, Mind, 37, 137–48.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Popper, K. R. (1945) The Open Society and Its Enemies, Volume 1, The Spell of Plato (London: Routledge and Kegan Paul).Google Scholar
Psillos, P. (1995): ‘Is Structural Realism the Best of Both Worlds?’, Dialectica, 49, 1546.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Redhead, M. L. G. (1995) From Physics to Metaphysics (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press).CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Resnick, M. D. (1997) Mathematics as a Science of Patterns (Oxford: Clarendon Press).Google Scholar
Rickart, C. E. (1995) Structuralism and Structures: A Mathematical Perspective (Singapore: World Scientific).CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Russell, B. (1927) The Analysis of Matter (London: Allen and Unwin).Google Scholar
Shapiro, S. (1997) Philosophy of Mathematics: Structure and Ontology (Oxford: Oxford University Press).Google Scholar
Solomon, (1989) ‘Discussion: An Addendum to Demopoulos and Friedman (1985)Philosophy of Science, 56, 497501.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Worrall, J. (1989) ‘Structural Realism: The Best of Both Worlds?’, Dialectica, 43, 99124.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Zahar, E. G. (1994) ‘Poincaré's Structural Realism and his Logic of Discovery’, in Heinzmann, G.et. al. (eds), Henri Poincaré: Akten Des Internationale Congresses, Nancy, 1994 (Berlin: Academie Verlag), pp. 45–68.Google Scholar