Hostname: page-component-8448b6f56d-c4f8m Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-04-23T20:51:29.827Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

Meaning and Evidence

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  05 May 2010

John C. Bigelow
Affiliation:
Victoria University of Wellington

Extract

What is it for a person to mean something by an utterance? Until recently, few philosophers have explicitly set themselves the task of answering this question. Of those who have, most have proposed answers which in one way or another analyze the act of meaning by appeal to the utterer's intentions.

Type
Articles
Copyright
Copyright © Canadian Philosophical Association 1976

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

References

1 Meaning”, The Philosophical Review, 66 (1957), pp. 377388CrossRefGoogle Scholar; Utterer's Meaning and Intentions”, The Philosophical Review, 78 (1969), pp. 147177CrossRefGoogle Scholar; Utterer's Meaning, Sentence-Meaning, and Word-Meaning”, Foundations of Language, 4 (1968), pp. 225242.Google Scholar

2 Meaning, Oxford, 1972.Google Scholar

3 Speech Acts, Cambridge, 1969Google Scholar; especially pp. 42–50.

4 Meaning and Communication”, The Philosophical Review, 80 (1971), pp. 427447.CrossRefGoogle Scholar

5 See for instance Grice, “Meaning”, pp. 385–386.

6 See for instance Armstrong, “Meaning and Communication”, pp. 443–444.

7 “Utterer's Meaning and Intentions”, pp. 152–165; also clause “III” on p. 176.

8 Meaning, p. 30 ff.

9 The Meaning-Nominalist Strategy”, Foundations of Language, 10 (1973), pp. 141168; also unpublished work which should appear soon as a book.Google Scholar