Hostname: page-component-8448b6f56d-tj2md Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-04-24T22:52:40.957Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

Emotions, Feelings and Contexts: A Reply to Robert Kraut*

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  13 April 2010

Robert C. Solomon
Affiliation:
University of Texas at Austin

Extract

Unwarranted antagonism between reason and the passions is an ancient problem, dating back at least to Plato. Even philosophers who sought to give the passions their due—David Hume for example—juxtaposed reason and emotion and contrasted them as slave and master (or vice versa). The point of a so-called “cognitive” theory of emotion, simply stated, is to deny this antagonism. The most succinct (if not very informative) statement of the cognitivist view is Nietzsche's: “as if every passion did not possess its quantum of reason.” Hume's own theory anticipated such a synthesis (in his awkward analysis of “ideas” as both necessary causes and effects of emotions) while Spinoza and Hobbes clearly defended cognitive theories with the wisdom of reconciliation in mind. The aim of a cognitive theory is not to reduce volatile emotion to cool and calm belief, nor is the emphasis on emotion a romantic attempt to extol the passions and excoriate reason—though that exercise may have its place in philosophy too; it is rather to understand reason and the passions together and appreciate their shared properties, similarities and complementarity as well as their obvious differences and oppositions. So understood, cognitive theories have, generically, gained widespread acceptance; only a few reactionaries in philosophy and psychology still insist on a cognition-free concept of emotion, however backhandedly cognitive concepts might be acknowledged as presuppositions, causal preconditions or criteria for the appropriate labelling of emotion rather than as proper constituents of emotion.

Type
Articles
Copyright
Copyright © Canadian Philosophical Association 1990

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

References

Notes

1 Nietzsche, Friedrich, The Will to Power, translated by Kaufmann, Walter (New York: Random House, 1967), p. 387.Google Scholar

2 Kraut, Robert, “Feelings in Context,” Journal of Philosophy, 83, 11 (November 1986): 642652.CrossRefGoogle Scholar

3 Walton, Kendall, “Fearing Fictions,” Journal of Philosophy, 75, 1 (January 1978), cited in Kraut, “Feelings in Context,” p. 642.CrossRefGoogle Scholar

4 Collingwood, R. G., The New Leviathan (New York: Oxford, 1947), p. 6768, cited in Kraut, “Feelings in Context,” p. 642.Google Scholar

5 Kraut, “Feelings in Context,” p. 651.

6 Since the writing of this paper, this enrichment of feeling has become more acceptable, e.g., see Greenspan, Patricia, Emotions and Reasons (London: Routledge, 1988)Google Scholar. As for the objection that mere thoughts of danger are sufficient to cause fear, I have argued elsewhere that such feelings do not constitute fear unless they also involve an underlying judgment that this is, indeed, a danger. See my “Beyond Reason: The Importance of Emotions in Philosophy,” in Revisioning Philosophy, edited by Ogilvy, J. (Albany: S.U.N.Y. Press, forthcoming).Google Scholar