Hostname: page-component-7c8c6479df-27gpq Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-03-28T13:26:30.860Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

Should Intentionality be Naturalized?

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  08 January 2010

Extract

One goal of recent philosophy of mind has been to ‘naturalize’ intentionality by showing how a purely physical system could have states that represent or are about items (objects, properties, facts) in the world. The project is reductionist in spirit, the aim being to explain intentional relations—to say what they really are—and to do so in terms that do not themselves utilize intentional or semantic concepts. In this vein there are attempts to explain intentional relations in terms of causal relations, informational relations, teleological or functional relations, relations involving abstract similarity or isomorphism, and various combinations thereof. What makes these accounts naturalistic is the presumed objectivity and scientific respectability of the properties appelated to in the explanans. What makes them all reductive is their shared presumption that intentionality can be explained in terms that have a wider application to intentional systems as well as to systems that have no mental properties at all.

Type
Papers
Copyright
Copyright © The Royal Institute of Philosophy and the contributors 2001

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

References

Antony, L. and Levine, J. 1997. ‘Reduction with Autonomy’, in Tomberlin, J. (ed.) Philosophical Perspectives 11: Mind, Causation, and World (Malden, MA: Blackwell Publishers), pp. 83105.Google Scholar
Beckerman, A., Flohr, H. and Kim, J. (eds) 1992. Emergence or Reduction? (Berlin: de Gruyter).CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Bennett, J. 1988. Events and Their Names (Indianapolis: Hackett Publishing Co.).Google Scholar
Block, N. (ed.) 1980. Readings in the Philosophy of Psychology I (Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press).Google Scholar
Brown, S. (ed.) 1974. Philosophy of Psychology (New York: The Macmillan Press).CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Cummins, R. 1996. Representations, Targets, and Attitudes (Cambridge, MA: MIT Press).CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Danto, A. 1967. ‘Naturalism’, in Edwards, P. (ed.) The Encyclopedia of Philosophy, Vol. 5, pp. 448–50.Google Scholar
Davidson, D. 1970. ‘Mental Events’, in Foster, L. and Swanson, J. (eds.) (Amherst, MA: The University of Massachusetts Press), pp. 79101.Google Scholar
Davidson, D. 1974. ‘Psychology as Philosophy’, in Brown, S. (ed.) (New York: The Macmillan Press), pp. 4152.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Davidson, D. 1993. ‘Thinking Causes’, in Heil, J. and Mele, A. (eds) (Oxford: Clarendon Press), pp. 317.Google Scholar
Dretske, F. 1981. Knowledge and the Flow of Information (Cambridge, MA: MIT Press).Google Scholar
Dretske, F. 1988. Explaining Behavior: Reasons in a World of Causes (Cambridge, MA: MIT Press).Google Scholar
Eells, E. 1991. Probabilistic Causality (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press).CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Fodor, J. 1984. ‘Semantics, Wisconsin Style’, Synthese, 59, 231–50.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Fodor, J. 1987. Psychosemantics. (Cambridge, MA: MIT Press).CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Foster, L. and Swanson, J. (eds) 1970. Experience and Theory (Amherst, MA: The University of Massachusetts Press).Google Scholar
Heil, J. and Mele, A. (eds) 1993. Mental Causation (Oxford: Clarendon Press).CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Horgan, T. 1993. ‘From Supervenience to Superdupervenience: Meeting the Demands of a Material World’, Mind, 102, 555–86.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Kim, J. 1971. ‘Causes and Events: Mackie on Causation’, Journal of Philosophy, 68, 426–41.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Kim, J. 1984. ‘Epiphenomenal and Supervenient Causation’, Midwest Studies in Philosophy, 9, 257–70. Reprinted in Kim (1993a).CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Kim, J. 1989. ‘The Myth of Nonreductive Materialism’, Proceedings and Addresses of the American Philosophical Association, 63, 3147. Reprinted in Kim (1993a).CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Kim, J. 1992. ‘Multiple Realizability and the Metaphysics of Reduction’, Philosophy and Phenomenological Research, 52, 126. Reprinted in Kim (1993a).CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Kim, J. 1993a. Supervenience and Mind (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press).CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Kim, J. 1993b. ‘Postscripts on Mental Causation’, in Kim (1993a), pp. 358–67.Google Scholar
Kim, J. 1998. Mind in a Physical World (Cambridge, MA: MIT Press).CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Lewis, D. 1973. ‘Causation’, Journal of Philosophy, 70, 556–67.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Lewis, D. 1980. ‘Mad Pain and Martian Pain’, in Block, N. (ed.) (Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press), pp. 216–22.Google Scholar
Mackie, J. 1965. ‘Causes and Conditions’, American Philosophical Quarterly, 2/4, 245–55 and 261–4.Google Scholar
McLaughlin, B. 1992. ‘The Rise and Fall of British Emergentism’, in Beckerman, A., Flohr, H., and Kim, J. (eds) (Berlin: de Gruyter), pp. 4993.Google Scholar
Millikan, R. 1984. Language, Thought, and Other Biological Categories (Cambridge, MA: MIT Press).CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Moore, G. E. 1922. ‘The Conception of Intrinsic Value’, in Philosophical Studies. (New York: Harcourt, Brace, and Co.), pp. 243–75.Google Scholar
Moore, G. E. 1942. ‘A Reply to My Critics’, in Schilpp, P. (ed.) The Philosophy of G. E. Moore (Evanston: Northwestern University Press), pp. 533677.Google Scholar
Oliver, W. 1949. ‘Can Naturalism Be Materialistic?’, Journal of Philosophy 46, 608–15.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Papineau, D. 1993. Philosophical Naturalism (Oxford: Blackwell).Google Scholar
Papineau, D. (forthcoming). ‘The Rise of Physicalism’.Google Scholar
Quine, W. V. 1969. ‘Epistemology Naturalized’, in Ontological Relativity and Other Essays (New York: Columbia University Press), pp. 6990.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Shapiro, L. 1997. ‘The Nature of Nature: Rethinking Naturalistic Theories of Intentionality’, Philosophical Psychology, 10, 309–22.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Shoemaker, S. 1981. ‘Some Varieties of Functionalism’, Philosophical Topics, 12, 93119.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Sober, E. 1999. ‘Physicalism from a Probabilistic Point of View’, Philosophical Studies, 95, 135–74.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Stampe, D. 1977. ‘Towards a Causal Theory of Linguistic Representation’, Midwest Studies in Philosophy, 2, 4263.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Stich, S. 1992. ‘What Is a Theory of Mental Representation?’, Mind, 101, 242–61.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Stich, S. and Laurence, S. 1994. ‘Intentionality and Naturalism’, Midwest Studies in Philosophy, 19, 159–82.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Tye, M. 1992. ‘Naturalism and the Mental’, Mind, 101, 421–41.CrossRefGoogle Scholar