Hostname: page-component-8448b6f56d-c47g7 Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-04-23T22:52:10.425Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

On Fire in Heraclitus and in Zeno of Citium

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  11 February 2009

R. W. Sharples
Affiliation:
University College London

Extract

In a recent discussion note1 C. D. C. Reeve investigates the reasons for Heraclitus assigning a primary position to fire, as contrasted with the other substances like earth and water which go to make up the physical universe. (I shall henceforth refer to these substances as ‘elements‘; the term is strictly incorrect for Heraclitus, in that the substances can change into one another, but it is a convenient form of shorthand.) Reeve considers and rejects other reasons for the primacy of fire that have been put forward, such as the symbolic associations of fire, the role of fire in governing the universe, or the claim that everything becomes fire at some time or other. Rather, Reeve argues, the primacy of fire in Heraclitus' physical theory can be explained purely in terms of that physical theory.

Type
Shorter Notes
Copyright
Copyright © The Classical Association 1984

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

References

1 Ekpyrosis and the priority of fire in Heraclitus’, Phronesis 27 (1982), 299305CrossRefGoogle Scholar.

2 Reeve argues that air, as well as earth, water and fire, is an ‘element’, one of the basic substances of which the universe is made up, for Heraclitus; this is debatable, but it does not seem to affect the general issue.

3 Anaximander, 12 A9 in Diels, H.Kranz, W., Die Fragmente der Vorsokratiker5 (Berlin, 1934)Google Scholar.

4 On which cf. Long, A. A., ‘Heraclitus and Stoicism’, Philosophia (Athens), 5–6 (19751976), 133–53Google Scholar.

5 von Arnim, J., Stoicorum Veterum Fragmenta (SVF) (Leipzig, 19031924), vol. iGoogle Scholar, no. 102; cf. Lapidge, M., ‘A problem in Stoic cosmology’, Phronesis 18 (1973), 240–78CrossRefGoogle Scholar.

6 SVF i. 157; Lapidge, , art. cit. pp. 253 fGoogle Scholar.

7 cf. Lapidge, , art. cit. pp. 267 f.Google Scholar; Sandbach, F. H., The Stoics (London, 1975), pp. 73 fGoogle Scholar. Chrysippus made matters more complex by introducing pneuma, a combination of fire and air, as the vehicle as it were of divine influence in the sublunary sphere; cf. Lapidge, , art. cit. pp. 273–8Google Scholar; Long, A. A., Hellenistic Philosophy (London, 1974), pp. 155 fGoogle Scholar.; and Todd, R. B., ‘Monism and Immanence’, in Rist, J. M. (ed.), The Stoics (Berkeley, 1978), pp. 148 ffGoogle Scholar.

8 This is the solution of Lapidge, , art. cit. pp. 268–73Google Scholar; cf. also Todd, , op. cit. p. 145Google Scholar, and Long, , art. cit. (n. 4), p. 140Google Scholar.

9 cf. Todd, , op. cit. pp. 143–8Google Scholar, on the embryological basis of Zeno's cosmology, and also Lapidge, , art. cit. p. 258Google Scholar: ‘Bodies might be less or more pure, depending on how much matter they contained, or depending on the relationship between the god and the matter’.

10 cf. Todd, , op. cit. p. 145Google Scholar. Lapidge, , art. cit. p. 258Google Scholar suggests that the passive, material principle may not be present in the creative divine fire at all; but, as he recognizes, this raises problems, and it does not seem to be required by the evidence.

11 In the second part of this note I have benefited greatly from the discussion at the colloquium on Stoic physics held in Cambridge in 1977.