Hostname: page-component-7c8c6479df-ws8qp Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-03-19T07:29:47.562Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

The Lysis on Loving One's Own

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  11 February 2009

David K. Glidden
Affiliation:
University of California, Riverside

Extract

Cicero, Lucullus 38: ‘…non potest animal ullum non adpetere id quod accommodatum ad naturam adpareat (Graeci id οỉκεῖον appellant)…’

From earliest childhood every man wants to possess something. One man collects horses. Another wants gold. Socrates has a passion for companions. He would rather have a good friend than a quail or a rooster. In this way, Socrates begins his interrogation of Menexenus. He then congratulates Menexenus and Lysis for each having what he himself still does not possess. How is it that one gets a friend, Socrates asks?

Since the nineteenth century many who have read these lines have found them repulsive. Scholars have damned the Lysis for its selfish egoism, for regarding persons as personal belongings. At the turn of the century some sought to discredit the dialogue as a forgery and a calumny. Others debated the dating of the dialogue as Socratic or Platonic, seeking whom to blame rather than whom to credit. And those who have regarded the dialogue as Platonic have tried to redeem it by detecting hints of Plato's theory of Forms. A few have attempted to salvage reputations by understanding the argument of the Lysis as a reductio of egoism, or else by invoking the loyalty of Socrates' friends and the history of Plato's friendship for Dion of Syracuse to speak up for their defence. Guthrie has condemned the dialogue as a failure of method and presentation (‘even Plato can nod’), and Vlastos has pronounced it a failure of love: ‘The lover Socrates has in view seems positively incapable of loving others for their own sake, else why must he feel no affection for anyone whose good-producing qualities he did not happen to need?’

The Lysis appears to make no positive contribution to the Greek tradition on friendship when compared to the Symposium or the Phaedrus. And in the subsequent tradition, whatever Aristotle might have borrowed from the dialogue he uses for his own purposes. Aristotle too is quite critical of specific points raised in the Lysis. Now it might seem that Aristotle made a place for the selfish love of the Lysis in his own theory, as an inferior grade of utility love. But even this cannot be so, if we are to agree with recent studies of Aristotle's ethics. According to Aristotle, if a client is friendly to his benefactor because of the latter's usefulness, this utilitarian motive must accompany a genuine concern (εὔνοια) for the benefactor's own interest in that relation, if they are to be friends. Inferior and genuine friendship may differ in purpose but not in regard for the well-being of the beloved. This respect for the object of one's love has no parallel in the Lysis, according to the standard reading of the dialogue.

Type
Research Article
Copyright
Copyright © The Classical Association 1981

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

References

(1)Adkins, A. W. H., ‘“Friendship” and “Self-Sufficiency” in Homer and Aristotle’, Classical Quarterly n.s. 13 (1963), 3045.Google Scholar
(2)Annas, J., ‘Plato and Aristotle on Friendship and Altruism’, Mind 86 (1977), 532–54.Google Scholar
(3)Anton, J. P. and Kustas, G. L. (eds.), Essays in Greek Philosophy (Albany, 1971).Google Scholar
(4)von Arnim, H., ‘Platos Lysis’, Rheinisches Museum 71 (1916), 364–87.Google Scholar
(5)Begemann, A. W., Plato's Lysis (Amsterdam, 1960).Google Scholar
(6)Boorse, C., ‘Wright on Functions’, Philosophical Review 85 (1976), 7086.Google Scholar
(7)Brink, C. O., ‘Oikeiosis and Oikeiotes: Theophrastus and Zeno on Nature in Moral Theory’, Phronesis 1 (1955/1956), 123–45.Google Scholar
(8)Brink, C. O., ‘Plato on the Natural Character of Goodness’, Harvard Studies in Classical Philology 63 (1958), 193–8.Google Scholar
(9)Chisholm, R. M., Perceiving (Ithaca, 1957).Google Scholar
(10)Cooper, J. M., ‘Aristotle on the Forms of Friendship’, Review of Metaphysics 30 (1977), 619–48.Google Scholar
(11)Cooper, J. M., ‘Friendship and the Good in Aristotle’, Philosophical Review 86 (1977), 290315.Google Scholar
(12)Dirlmeier, F., ‘Philos und Philia im vorhellenistischen Griechentum’ (Munich: In.-Diss., 1931).Google Scholar
(13)Dover, K. J., Greek Popular Morality (Oxford, 1974).Google Scholar
(14)Düring, I. and Owen, G. E. L. (eds.), Aristotle and Plato in the Mid-Fourth Century (Göteborg, 1960).Google Scholar
(15)Fraisse, J.-C., Philia: la notion d' amitié dans la philosophie antique (Paris, 1974), pp. 128–50.Google Scholar
(16)Glaser, K., ‘Gang und Ergebnis des Platonischen Lysis’, Wiener Studien 53 (1935), 4767.Google Scholar
(17)Glidden, D. K., ‘The Language of Love: Lysis 212a8–213c9’, Pacific Philosophical Quarterly 61 (1980), 276290.Google Scholar
(18)Grote, G., Plato, i (London, 1865).Google Scholar
(19)Guthrie, W. K. C., A History of Greek Philosophy, iv (Cambridge, 1975).Google Scholar
(20)Hardie, W. F. R., Aristotle's Ethical Theory (Oxford, 1968).Google Scholar
(21)Hoerber, R. G., ‘Plato's Lysis’, Phronesis 4 (1959), 1528.Google Scholar
(22)Hyland, D. A., ‘Eros, Epithumia, and Philia in Plato’, Phronesis 13 (1968), 3246.Google Scholar
(23)Irwin, T., Plato's Moral Theory (Oxford, 1977).Google Scholar
(24)Levin, D. N., ‘Some Observations Concerning Plato's Lysis’, (1964) in (3), pp. 236–58.Google Scholar
(25)Long, A. A. (ed.), Problems in Stoicism (London, 1971).Google Scholar
(26)Owen, G. E. L., ‘Logic and Metaphysics in Some Earlier Works of Aristotle’, in (14), pp. 163–90.Google Scholar
(27)Pembroke, S. G., ‘Oikeiosis’, in (25), pp. 114–49.Google Scholar
(28)Robinson, R., ‘Plato's Consciousness of Fallacy’, Mind 51 (1942), 97114.Google Scholar
(29)Santas, G., ‘The Socratic Paradoxes’, Philosophical Review 73 (1964), 147–64.Google Scholar
(30)Schoplick, V., ‘Der Platonische Dialog Lysis’ (Augsburg: In.-Diss., 1968).Google Scholar
(31)Shorey, P., What Plato Said (Chicago, 1965).Google Scholar
(32)Versenyi, L., ‘Plato's Lysis’, Phronesis 20 (1975), 185–98.Google Scholar
(33)Vlastos, G., Platonic Studies (Princeton, 1973).Google Scholar
(34)Wright, L., ‘Functions’, Philosophical Review 82 (1973), 139–68.Google Scholar
(35)Wright, L., Teleological Explanation (Berkeley and Los Angeles, 1976).Google Scholar