Hostname: page-component-7c8c6479df-nwzlb Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-03-27T18:56:40.268Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

Healthy Scepticism

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  30 January 2009

James Franklin
Affiliation:
University of New South Wales

Extract

Like Platonism in the philosophy of mathematics, or Communism in California, scepticism about the external world is a doctrine that maintains its health not by being held by many, but by being attacked often. Though there were actual sceptics in ancient times, in various degrees, the history of scepticism in medieval and modern times has been entirely a history of arguments, not of schools.

Type
Articles
Copyright
Copyright © The Royal Institute of Philosophy 1991

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

References

1 Herbert, E., Herbert of Cherbury, De Veritate trans. Carré, M. H. (Bristol: Arrowsmith, 1937), 83.Google Scholar

2 Taylor, R., Metaphysics (Englewood Cliffs, N.J.: Prentice Hall, 2nd ed., 1974), 114–9.Google Scholar

3 References in Compton, J. J., ‘Some contributions of existential phenomenology to the philosophy of natural science’, American Philosophical Quarterly 25 (1988), 99113Google Scholar; also Franklin, J., ‘Natural sciences as textual interpretation’, Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 44 (1984), 509520.CrossRefGoogle Scholar

4 Kenny, A., Aquinas (Oxford University Press, 1980), ch. 3.Google Scholar

5 Cicero, , Academica II. 84.Google Scholar

6 Stroud, B., The Significance of Philosophical Scepticism (Oxford: Clarendon, 1984), 89.CrossRefGoogle Scholar

7 Williams, D. C., The Ground of Induction (N.Y.: Russell & Russell, 1963)Google Scholar; Stove, D. C., The Rationality of Induction (Oxford: Clarendon, 1986).Google Scholar

8 Berkeley, G., Principles of Human Knowledge, sec. 20.Google Scholar

9 Odegard, D., ‘Demon Scepticism’, American Philosophical Quarterly 23 (1986), 209216.Google Scholar

10 Nozick, R., Philosophical Explanations (Oxford: Clarendon, 1981), especially 240243.Google Scholar

11 Moser, P. K., ‘Two roads to skepticism’, in Doubting, Roth, M. D. and Ross, G. (eds) (Dordrecht: Kluwer, 1990), 127139, at 133.CrossRefGoogle Scholar

12 Slote, M. A., Reason and Scepticism (London: Allen & Unwin, 1970), 62, with further references.Google Scholar

13 Vogel, J., ‘Cartesian skepticism and inference to the best explanation’, Journal of Philosophy 87 (1990), 658666.CrossRefGoogle Scholar

14 Slote, , 66.Google Scholar

15 Quine, W. V., ‘The nature of natural knowledge’, in Mind and Language, Guttenplan, S., (ed.), (Oxford: Clarendon, 1975), 67.Google Scholar

16 Quine, W. V., Word and Object (Cambridge, Mass: Technology Press, 1960), 275276.Google Scholar

17 Pollock, J., Knowledge and Justification (Princeton University Press, 1975), 65.Google Scholar

18 Johnsen, B. C., ‘Relevant alternatives and demon scepticism’, in Doubting, Roth, M. D. and Ross, G. (eds), (Dordrecht: Kluwer, 1990), 2937, at 31.CrossRefGoogle Scholar

19 Grayling, A. C., The Refutation of Scepticism (London: Duckworth, 1985), 91.Google Scholar

20 Grayling, , 3.Google Scholar

21 Spelke, E. S., ‘Perception of unity, persistence, and identity: Thoughts on infants' conceptions of objects’, in Neonate Cognition, Mehler, J. and Fox, R. (ed.) (Hillsdale, N.J.: Erlbaum, 1985), ch. 6Google Scholar; Baillargeon, R. et al. , ‘Why do young infants fail to search for hidden objects?’, Cognition 36 (1990), 255284CrossRefGoogle Scholar; Harris, P. L., ‘Object permanence in infants’, in The Psychology of Infancy, A. Slater and J. G. Bremmer, (ed.), in press.Google Scholar

22 Rescher, N., Scepticism, Oxford: Blackwell, 1980), 163–4.Google Scholar

23 Rescher, , 169.Google Scholar

24 Rescher, , 79.Google Scholar

25 Johnsen, , 35.Google Scholar

26 Aquinas, Thomas, Summa Theologiae Part 1 q. 89 art. 7.Google Scholar

27 Armstrong, D. M., Perception and the Physical World (London: Routledge, 1961), 29.Google Scholar

28 Barr, A. and Feigenbaum, E. A., (eds.), The Handbook of Artificial Intelligence (Stanford: Heuris Tech, 1981), vol. IGoogle Scholar section III A and vol. III section XIII D; Marr, D., Vision: A Computational Investigation into the Human Representation and Processing of Visual Information (San Francisco: Freeman, 1982)Google Scholar; Pentland, A. P., editor's introduction to From Pixels to Predicates (Norwood, N.J.: Ablex, 1986)Google Scholar; Rumelhart, D. E., Hinton, G. E. & Williams, R. J., ‘Learning internal representations by back-propagating errors’, Nature 323 (1986), 533536.CrossRefGoogle Scholar

29 Fakhry, M., Islamic Occasionalism (London: Allen & Unwin, 1958), 46Google Scholar; cf. van Ess, J., ‘Skepticism in Islamic religious thought’, Al-Abhath 21 (1968), 118.Google Scholar

30 Fakhry, , 28.Google Scholar

31 Averroes' ‘Tahafut al-Tahafut’, trans. van den Bergh, S. (London: Luzac, 1954), vol. I, 316317.Google Scholar

32 Quine, W. V., From a Logical Point of View (Cambridge, Mass: Harvard University Press, 1953), 44.Google Scholar

33 Augustine, , City of God bk 18 ch. 18Google Scholar; cf. Aquinas, Thomas, Quaestiones Disputatae de Malo q. 16 art. 11.Google Scholar

34 Kramer, H. and Sprenger, J., Malleus Maleficarum, trans. Summers, M. (London: Rodker, 1928, repr. N.Y.: Dover, 1971), 5859; cf. 119, 125.Google Scholar

35 Lea, H. C., Materials Towards a History of Witchcraft (N.Y.: Yoseloff 1957), vol. 1, 356357.Google Scholar

36 James, VI and I, Daemonologie (Edinburgh, 1597, repr. Edinburgh Edinburgh University Press, 1966), 7980.Google Scholar