Hostname: page-component-76fb5796d-dfsvx Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-04-25T17:39:25.098Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

On the Synthetic Aspect of Mathematics

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  25 February 2009

Extract

In the most recent edition of Language, Truth and Logic, Professor A. J. Ayer still maintains that pure mathematics is analytic, being in fact merely a vast system of tautology. He is much more confident about this than are most contemporary professional mathematicians who have investigated the foundations of their subject. Following the breakdown of the efforts both of Frege and of Russell and Whitehead to derive pure mathematics from logic, i.e. to prove that the denial of any one proposition of mathematics would necessarily be self-contradictory, Hilbert attempted to prove the more modest thesis that pure mathematics is consistent, i.e. that no two propositions of mathematics can contradict each other; but in 1931 Gödel discovered that even this thesis was undecidable according to the “rules of the game.” As Weyl has recently lamented, “From this history one thing should be clear: we are less certain than ever about the ultimate foundations of (logic and) mathematics.”

The sense in which Ayer uses the terms analytic and tautology implies also that in his view the activities of pure mathematicians lead to nothing new. It is true that he remarks that “there is a sense in which analytic propositions do give us new knowledge. They call attention to linguistic usages of which we might otherwise not be conscious, and they reveal unsuspected implications in our assertions and beliefs.” But, he continues, “we can also see that there is a sense in which they may be said to add nothing to our knowledge. For they may be said to tell us what we know already. ” This denial of novelty in mathematics is as typical of contemporary positivism as the prophecy of Comte that the composition of the stars would never be revealed to us and the objections of Mach to the atomic hypothesis were characteristic of nineteenth century positivism. Indeed, one wonders why the term positivism should have been appropriated by successive philosophers whose common outlook could be so much more fittingly described as negativism.

Type
Articles
Copyright
Copyright © The Royal Institute of Philosophy 1950

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

References

page 326 note 1 Ayer, A. J., Language, Truth and Logic. London, 1948, pp. 7587Google Scholar.

page 326 note 2 Weyl, H., American Mathematical Monthly, 53 (1946), p. 13Google Scholar.

page 326 note 3 Ayer, A. J., op. cit., pp. 79–80.

page 327 note 1 Ayer, A. J., op, cit., p. 86.

page 328 note 1 Pelseneer, J., Esquisse du Progrès de la Pensée Mathimatique. Paris, 1935. p. 91Google Scholar.

page 328 note 2 Ayer, A. J., op. cit., pp. 77 et seq.

page 328 note 3 Cassirer, E., Substance and Function. Chicago, 1923. p. 7Google Scholar.

page 329 note 1 Ayer, A. J., op. cit., p. 85.

page 329 note 2 Hardy, G. H., Ramanujan. Cambridge, 1940, p. 11Google Scholar.

page 330 note 1 Birkhoff, G. D., Aesthetic Measure. Harvard, 1933CrossRefGoogle Scholar. For a recent account of Renaissance views on this question, see Blunt, A., Artistic Theory in Italy, 1450–1600. Oxford, 1940Google Scholar.

page 330 note 2 Unlike Kant, of course, we no longer regard the construction of, and appeal to, the figure as an essential feature of a geometrical proof.