Hostname: page-component-8448b6f56d-cfpbc Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-04-18T14:15:37.666Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

How Far is it from Virginia and Rochester to Frankfurt? Public Choice as Critical Theory

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  27 January 2009

Extract

Public choice and critical theory constitute two very different and often mutually hostile research traditions. An opportunity for conversation across the two traditions arises inasmuch as public choice has itself demonstrated the incoherence of a politics – in particular, a democratic politics – of unconstrained rational egoism. By deploying an expanded, communicative conception of rationality, critical theory can help move public choice beyond several related impasses. Critical theory benefits from this encounter by gaining content for its currently rather abstract critiques of politics and rationality, and additional insight into the forces conducive to different kinds of rationality. More importantly, political science stands to gain an account of politics more powerful than either tradition can muster by itself.

Type
Articles
Copyright
Copyright © Cambridge University Press 1992

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

References

1 Almond, Gabriel A., A Discipline Divided: Schools and Sects in Political Science (Beverly Hills, Calif.: Sage, 1990), p. 19.Google Scholar

2 Riker, William H., ‘The Two-Party System and Duverger's Law: An Essay on the History of Political Science’, American Political Science Review, 76 (1982), 753–66, p. 753.CrossRefGoogle Scholar

3 Bohman, James, ‘Communication, Ideology, and Democratic Theory’, American Political Science Review, 84 (1990), 93109, p. 107CrossRefGoogle Scholar. One of the first attempts at dialogue across the two traditions is made by White, Stephen K., ‘Toward a Critical Political Science’, in Ball, Terence, ed., Idioms of Inquiry: Critique and Renewal in Political Science (Albany: State University of New York Press, 1987)Google Scholar. White treats rational choice and critical theory as rival research programmes. He argues that critical theory outperforms its rival in two problem areas: the long-running community power debate, and the dynamics of modernization. More recently, Johnson, James, ‘Rational Choice as a Reconstructive Theory’, in Monroe, Kristen, ed., The Economic Approach to Politics (New York: Harper Collins, 1991)Google Scholar has interpreted rational choice's game theory in terms of critical theory's reconstructive science category.

4 Dogan, Mattei and Pahre, Robert, Creative Marginality: Innovation at the Intersection of Social Sciences (Boulder, Col.: Westview, 1990).Google Scholar

5 MacIntyre, Alasdair, Whose Justice? Which Rationality? (Notre Dame, Ind.: University of Notre Dame Press, 1988), pp. 364–5.Google Scholar

6 Political order should here be taken to mean political institutions that produce collective choices in consistent, non-dictatorial and non-violent fashion, and that can lay claim to public legitimacy.

7 For a review of the Rochester School, focusing on Riker, see Weale, Albert, ‘Social Choice Versus Populism? An Interpretation of Riker's Political Theory’, British Journal of Political Science, 14 (1984), 369–85CrossRefGoogle Scholar. For more general surveys of public choice, see McLean, Iain, ‘Some Recent Work in Public Choice’, British Journal of Political Science, 16 (1986), 377–94CrossRefGoogle Scholar, and Mitchell, William C., ‘Virginia, Rochester, and Bloomington: Twenty-Five Years of Public Choice and Political Science’, Public Choice, 56 (1988), 101–19.CrossRefGoogle Scholar

8 More complete histories of the Frankfurt School may be found in Jay, Martin, The Dialectical Imagination: A History of the Frankfurt School and the Institute of Social Research, 1923–1950 (Boston, Mass.: Little, Brown, 1973)Google Scholar and Held, David, Introduction to Critical Theory: Horkheimer to Habermas (London: Hutchinson, 1980)Google Scholar. For an excellent account of critical theory more generally, see Leonard, Stephen T., Critical Theory in Political Practice (Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press, 1990)Google Scholar. Critical theory of the sort under discussion here should not be confused with the efforts of Derrideans and deconstructionists in literary theory, who have unfortunately tried to appropriate the term.

9 There are feminists who would say that this really is a model of man.

10 Bohman, James, ‘Participating in Enlightenment: Habermas's Cognitivist Interpretation of Democracy’, in Dascal, Marcelo and Gruengard, Ora, eds, Knowledge and Politics (Boulder, Col.: Westview, 1989), p. 270.Google Scholar

11 White, , ‘Toward a Critical Political Science’, p. 117.Google Scholar

12 Marcuse, Herbert, One Dimensional Man (Boston, Mass.: Beacon Press, 1964).Google Scholar

13 Horkheimer, Max and Adorno, Theodor, Dialectic of Enlightenment (New York: Herder and Herder, 1972).Google Scholar

14 Buchanan, James M., ‘Politics Without Romance: A Sketch of Positive Public Choice and its Normative Implications’, in Hamlin, Alan and Pettit, Philip, eds, Contemporary Political Theory (New York: Macmillan, 1991), p. 217.Google Scholar

15 Moon, J. Donald, ‘The Logic of Political Inquiry: A Synthesis of Opposed Perspectives’, in Greenstein, Fred I. and Polsby, Nelson W., eds, Handbook of Political Science, vol. 1 (Reading, Mass.: Addison-Wesley, 1975)Google Scholar; Ball, Terence, ‘From Paradigms to Research Programs: Toward a Post-Kuhnian Political Science’, American Journal of Political Science, 20 (1976), 151–77.CrossRefGoogle Scholar

16 Riker, , ‘The Two-Party System’Google Scholar; Mitchell, , ‘Virginia, Rochester, and Bloomington’, pp. 102–6.Google Scholar

17 Buchanan, , ‘Politics Without Romance’, p. 217.Google Scholar

18 See also Johnson, , ‘Rational Choice as a Reconstructive Theory’.Google Scholar

19 Habermas, Jürgen, Knowledge and Human Interests (Boston, Mass.: Beacon Press, 1971)Google Scholar; Fay, Brian, Social Theory and Political Practice (London: George Allen and Unwin, 1975), pp. 2947.Google Scholar

20 Almond, , A Discipline Divided, pp. 1617Google Scholar; Buchanan, , ‘Politics Without Romance’.Google Scholar

21 Brennan, Geoffrey, ‘Politics With Romance: Towards a Theory of Democratic Socialism’, in Pettit, Philip, ed., The Good Polity: Normative Analysis of the State (Oxford: Basil Blackwell, 1989), p. 63.Google Scholar

22 Wittman, Donald, ‘Why Democracies Produce Efficient Outcomes’, Journal of Political Economy, 97 (1989), 13951424, p. 1395, n. 1.CrossRefGoogle Scholar

23 Arrow, Kenneth J., Social Choice and Individual Values, rev. edn. (New York: Wiley, 1963).Google Scholar

24 Riker, William H., Liberalism Against Populism: A Confrontation Between the Theory of Democracy and the Theory of Social Choice (San Francisco: W. H. Freeman, 1982), p. 241.Google Scholar

25 Buchanan, James M. and Tullock, Gordon, The Calculus of Consent (Ann Arbor: University of Michigan Press, 1962)CrossRefGoogle Scholar. A situation is Pareto optimal when no individual can be made better off without making some other individual worse off. The criterion is much favoured by welfare economists, who generally argue that perfect markets produce this kind of outcome.

26 Niskanen, William A., Bureaucracy and Representative Government (Chicago: Aldine-Atherton, 1971).Google Scholar

27 Fiorina, Morris P., Congress: Keystone of the Washington Establishment (New Haven, Conn.: Yale University Press, 1977).Google Scholar

28 Friedman, Milton and Friedman, Rose, Tyranny of the Status Quo (New York: Harcourt Brace Jovanovich, 1984).Google Scholar

29 Mitchell, , ‘Virginia, Rochester, and Bloomington’, p. 108.Google Scholar

30 Olson, Mancur, The Rise and Decline of Nations: Economic Growth, Stagflation, and Social Rigidities (New Haven, Conn.: Yale University Press, 1983).Google Scholar

31 Barry, Brian and Hardin, Russell, eds, Rational Man and Irrational Society? (Beverly Hills, Calif.: Sage, 1982).Google Scholar

32 Riker, , Liberalism Against Populism, p. xviii.Google Scholar

33 Brennan, , ‘Politics With Romance’.Google Scholar

34 Brennan, , ‘Politics With Romance’, p. 62.Google Scholar

35 For Brennan, politicians should actually believe these principles, and not just act as if they believed them. A similar function is performed by Downs's argument that rational parties should espouse ideologies of some stability, because otherwise rational voters would not believe that parties will keep their election-time promises. See Downs, Anthony, An Economic Theory of Democracy (New York: Harper and Row, 1957)Google Scholar. But for Downs, it is not necessary for politicians to actually believe in their ideologies.

36 Bohman, , ‘Communication, Ideology’, p. 107.Google Scholar

37 To use the title of Mitchell, William C., Government As It Is (London: Institute of Economic Affairs, 1988).Google Scholar

38 Habermas, Jürgen, The Theory of Communicative Action I: Reason and the Rationalization of Society (Boston, Mass.: Beacon Press, 1984).Google Scholar

39 Brennan, , ‘Politics With Romance’.Google Scholar

40 Vanberg, Viktor and Buchanan, James M., ‘Interests and Theories in Constitutional Choice’, Journal of Theoretical Politics, 1 (1989), 4962.CrossRefGoogle Scholar

41 Vanberg, and Buchanan, , ‘Interests and Theories’, p. 59.Google Scholar

42 Vanberg, and Buchanan, , ‘Interests and Theories’, p. 60.Google Scholar

43 Vanberg, and Buchanan, , ‘Interests and Theories’, p. 60.Google Scholar

44 Critical theorists themselves would also point to the influence here of education, the experience of participation in collective life, the increasing availability of information, the reduced pressure of subsistence needs and the diffusion of democratic ideas.

45 Cultural variability in other kinds of societies may limit instrumental rationality. See Almond, , A Discipline Divided, pp. 134–5.Google Scholar

46 Arguably, public choice implicitly warrants further behavioural constraints by treating particular kinds of maximization as inevitable in particular locations. So consumers maximize utility through consumption, producers maximize profits, bureaucrats maximize budgets, politicians maximize their probability of election and re-election, citizens maximize benefits to themselves by choosing among candidates for office (assuming they are irrational enough to vote) and so forth. Hindess, Barry, Political Choice and Social Structure (Aldershot, Hants.: Edward Elgar, 1989), pp. 5660Google Scholar, claims that public choice is guilty of a kind of structural determinism, in which individual behaviour and the shape of individual preference ordering (be it cardinal, ordinal or lexical) is caused by one's place in established social structures, rather than freely chosen. In reply to Hindess, it must be said that rational choice theorists simply point out that choice occurs within a contextually-constrained feasible set, which is not the same as requiring that the individual's method of choice be structurally determined. Public choice also allows that individuals may seek to manipulate the parameters of structural situations; see Riker, William H., ‘The Heresthetics of Constitution-Making: The Presidency in 1787, with Comments on Determinism and Rational Choice’, American Political Science Review, 78 (1984), 116.CrossRefGoogle Scholar

47 Dawes, R., McTavish, J. and Shaklee, H., ‘Behavior, Communications, and Assumptions About Other Peoples' Behavior in a Commons Dilemma Situation’, Journal of Personality and Social Psychology, 35 (1977), 111CrossRefGoogle Scholar; Orbell, John M., van de Kragt, Alphons J. C. and Dawes, Robyn M., ‘Explaining Discussion-Induced Cooperation in Social Dilemmas’, Journal of Personality and Social Psychology, 54 (1988), 811–19.CrossRefGoogle Scholar

48 Baseline and discussion-induced co-operation rates are not a function of subjects interacting outside the experiment. The Orbell-Dawes experiments do not recruit their subjects from undergraduate classes but rather through newspaper advertisements. Real money is at stake and care is taken to ensure that participants in each group are strangers to one another, with no particular likelihood of future interaction.

49 Orbell, John M., Dawes, Robyn M. and van de Kragt, Alphons J. C., ‘The Limits of Multilateral Promising’, Ethics, 100(1990), 616–27.CrossRefGoogle Scholar

50 Buchanan, James M., ‘Then and Now, 1961–1986: From Delusion to Dystopia’, paper presented at the Institute for Humane Studies, 1986Google Scholar, quoted in Mansbridge, Jane J., ‘The Rise and Fall of Self-interest in the Explanation of Political Life’, in Mansbridge, Jane J., ed, Beyond Self-Interest (Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1990), p. 21.Google Scholar

51 Hirschman, Albert O., The Passions and the Interests: Political A rgumentsfor Capitalism Before its Triumph (Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press, 1977).Google Scholar

52 Mansbridge, Jane J., Beyond Adversary Democracy (Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1980).Google Scholar

53 Dryzek, John S., Discursive Democracy: Politics, Policy, and Political Science (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1990), pp. 3848.Google Scholar

54 Dryzek, , Discursive Democracy, pp. 37–8, 4850.Google Scholar

55 Barber, Benjamin, Strong Democracy: Participatory Politics for a New Age (Berkeley: University of California Press, 1984).Google Scholar

56 Mansbridge, , Beyond Adversary Democracy.Google Scholar

57 Forester, John, Planning in the Face of Power (Berkeley: University of California Press, 1989).Google Scholar

58 Kelman, Steven, ‘“Public Choice” and Public Spirit’, The Public Interest, 87 (1987), 8094.Google Scholar

59 Hardin, Russell, ‘Review Article: Constitutional Political Economy – Agreement on Rules’, British Journal of Political Science, 18 (1988), 513–30, p. 515.CrossRefGoogle Scholar

60 Buchanan and others draw a sharp distinction between ‘constitutional’ and ‘in-period’ collective choice. They hope that constitutional choice will involve such uncertainty about the effects of different arrangements on particular individuals' well-being that each individual will behave in impartial fashion. This hope contradicts the public choice literature on rent-seeking, which argues that individuals will seek rules favourable to themselves; see Vanberg, and Buchanan, , ‘Interests and Theories’, p. 53.Google Scholar

61 Smith, Adam, An Inquiry into the Nature and Causes of the Wealth of Nations (Oxford: Clarendon, 1976 [1776]).Google Scholar

62 Friedman, Milton and Friedman, Rose, Free to Choose (New York: Harcourt Brace Jovanovich, 1979), p. 30.Google Scholar

63 Smith, Adam, The Theory of Moral Sentiments (Oxford: Clarenden, 1976[1759]).Google Scholar

64 Rawls, John, A Theory of Justice (Cambridge, Mass.: Harvard University Press, 1971)Google Scholar; Gauthier, David, Morals by Agreement (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1985).Google Scholar

65 Phillipson, Nicholas, ‘Adam Smith as a Civic Moralist’, in Hont, Istvan and Ignatieff, Michael, eds, Wealth and Virtue: The Shaping of Political Economy in the Scottish Enlightenment (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1983), p. 183.Google Scholar

66 A century later, Edgeworth would argue, relatedly, that the economic calculus is appropriate only to war and contract; see Sen, Amartya K., ‘Rational Fools: A Critique of the Behavioral Foundations of Economic Theory’, in Harris, H., ed., Scientific Models and Man (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1978), p. 317.Google Scholar

67 Smith, , Theory of Moral Sentiments, p. 342.Google Scholar

68 Hont, Istvan and Ignatieff, Michael, ‘Needs and Justice in The Wealth of NationsGoogle Scholar, in Hont, and Ignatieff, , eds, Wealth and Virtue, pp. 910.Google Scholar

69 Winch, Donald, ‘Adam Smith's “Enduring Particular Result”: A Political and Cosmopolitan Perspective’Google Scholar, in Hont, and Ignatieff, , eds, Wealth and Virtue, p. 260.Google Scholar

70 Elster, Jon, Making Sense of Marx (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1985)Google Scholar; Przeworski, Adam, Capitalism and Social Democracy (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1985)CrossRefGoogle Scholar; Roemer, John, ed., Analytical Marxism (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1986).Google Scholar

71 Weldes, Jutta, ‘Marxism and Methodological Individualism: A Critique’, Theory and Society, 18 (1989), 353–86, p. 373.CrossRefGoogle Scholar

72 Elster, Jon, ‘Marxism and Individualism’Google Scholar, in Dascal, and Gruengard, , eds, Knowledge and Politics, p. 193.Google Scholar

73 Barry, and Hardin, , Rational Man and Irrational Society?, p. 383.Google Scholar

74 Downs, , An Economic Theory of Democracy.Google Scholar

75 Riker, William H. and Ordeshook, Peter C., ‘A Theory of the Calculus of Voting’, American Political Science Review, 72 (1968), 2542, p. 28.CrossRefGoogle Scholar

76 Enelow, James and Hinich, Melvin, The Spatial Theory of Voting (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1984), p. 221.Google Scholar

77 Brennan, , ‘Politics With Romance’.Google Scholar

78 Buchanan, , ‘Then and Now’.Google Scholar

79 Vanberg, and Buchanan, , ‘Interests and Theories’.Google Scholar

80 Elster, Jon, ‘The Market and the Forum’, in Elster, Jon and Hylland, Aanud, eds, Foundations of Social Choice Theory (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1986), p. 114.Google Scholar