Hostname: page-component-7c8c6479df-24hb2 Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-03-28T15:09:49.779Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

Reconsidering the Relationship among Voluntary Acts, Strict Liability, and Negligence in Criminal Law

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  13 January 2009

Larry Alexander
Affiliation:
Lam, University of San Diego

Extract

This essay, as will become obvious, owes a huge debt to Mark Kelman, particularly to his article “Interpretative Construction in the Substantive Criminal Law.” That debt is one of both concept and content. There is rich irony in my aping Kelman's deconstructionist enterprise, for I do not share his enthusiasm for either the “insights” or the political agenda of the Critical Legal Studies movement. I do not believe that either the law in general or the criminal law in particular is radically indeterminate, rife with internal contradictions, or an expression of the interests of a dominant economic class. And although, like Kelman, I believe that the freedom/determinism, act/character, and rule/principle dichotomies must ultimately be dealt with in order to have a completely satisfactory account of criminal law, I also believe that these dichotomies loom just as large in other areas of law and in normative theory generally. They are problems for Crits as well as for liberal-legalists.

In any event, my intentions in undertaking this deconstructionist enterprise are modestly reformist, not revolutionary. I do not intend to shift any paradigms, but to work with well-established ones. I will assume that criminal law seeks to accomplish some blend of retributive response to and deterrence of culpable choices, choices to defy moral norms that are also legal norms. (I omit consideration of criminal laws premised on immoral norms.) I will also assume that a culpable choice is one that reflects negatively on the values held by the chooser. Beyond these quite modest assumptions, I need not and will not venture in this paper, realizing, of course, that much has and can be written about the proper aims of punishment and the proper account of culpability.

Type
Research Article
Copyright
Copyright © Social Philosophy and Policy Foundation 1990

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

References

1 Stanford Law Review, vol. 33 (April 1981), pp. 591–673. See also Kelman, Mark, A Guide to Critical Legal Studies (Cambridge: Harvard University Press, 1987), pp. 15185.Google Scholar

2 See Hager, Mark, “Against Liberal Ideology,” American University Law Review, vol. 37 (Summer 1988), pp. 1051, 1057–58.Google Scholar

Briefly, the freedom/determinism dichotomy refers to the philosophical issue of whether determinism prevails throughout nature, including the realm of human action, or whether human action is indeterministic is some sense, and what resolution of these questions entails for moral responsibility. The act/character dichotomy refers to the issue of whether moral responsibility is ultimately a function of how we act or a function of what kind of character we have. The rule/principle dichotomy refers to the issue of whether we should be guided in each of our acts by our ultimate moral principles, or whether we should be guided by rules that are more determinate than those principles but that lead to some acts that from the standpoint of the principles would be judged to be morally wrong.

3 See Hampton, Jean, “Mens Rea,” Social Philosophy & Policy, vol. 7, no. 2 (Spring 1990).Google Scholar

4 Dressier, Joshua, Understanding Criminal Law (New York, Oakland, and Albany: Matthew Bender, 1987), p. 65.Google Scholar

5 ibid.

6 Performance of a mental ritual might also qualify. See Katz, Leo, Bad Acts and Guilty Minds: Conundrums of the Criminal Law (Chicago and London: University of Chicago Press, 1987).CrossRefGoogle Scholar

7 Dressier, , Understanding Criminal Law, pp. 6768Google Scholar; Hart, H.L.A., Punishment and Responsibility (New York: Oxford University Press, 1968), pp. 9596, 150–51Google Scholar; Perkins, Rollin and Boyce, Ronald, Criminal Law (Mineola: Foundation Press, 3rd ed. 1982), p. 837.Google Scholar

8 Model Penal Code, § 2.01 (Proposed Official Draft 1962).

9 ibid., § 1.13(2).

10 ibid, § 2.01.

11 Hart, , Punishment and Responsibility, p. 99.Google Scholar

12 The United States Supreme Court held that the federal constitutional prohibition of “cruel and unusual punishments” prevented criminalizing the status of narcotics addiction. Robinson v. California, 370 U.S. 660, 82 S.Q. 1417, 8 L.Ed.2d 758 (1966). The orthodox interpretation of the Robinson decision is that it rests on the distinction between punishing statuses and punishing acts. See, e.g., Dressier, , Understanding Criminal Law, pp. 7377.Google Scholar

13 Husak, Douglas, Philosophy of Criminal Law (Totowa: Rowman and Littlefield, 1987), ch. 4.Google Scholar

14 Perkins, and Boyce, , Criminal Law, pp. 896, 899.Google Scholar

15 LaFave, Wayne and Scott, Austin, Criminal Law (St. Paul: West Publishing, 3rd ed. 1986), p. 242.Google Scholar

16 Lewis, David, “The Punishment That Leaves Something to Chance,” Philosophy & Public Affairs, vol. 18, no. 1 (Winter 1988), pp. 5367Google Scholar; Sverdlik, Steven, “Crime and Moral Luck,” American Philosophical Quarterly, vol. 25, no. 1 (January 1988), pp. 7985Google Scholar; Ashworth, Andrew, “Criminal Attempts and the Role of Resulting Harm Under the Code, and in the Common Law,” Rutgers Law Journal, vol. 19, no. 3 (Spring 1988), pp. 725810Google Scholar; Shachar, Yoram, “The Fortuitous Gap in Law and Morality,” Criminal Justice Ethics, vol. 6, no. 2 (Summer/Fall 1987), pp. 1236CrossRefGoogle Scholar; Note, , “Chance, Freedom, and Criminal Liability,” Columbia Law Review, vol. 87, no. 1 (January 1987), pp. 125–41Google Scholar; Thomson, Judith, “The Decline of Cause,” The Georgetown Law Journal, vol. 76 (1987), pp. 137–50Google Scholar; Rothstein, Paul, “Causation in Torts, Crimes, and Moral Philosophy: A Reply to Professor Thomson,” The Georgetown Law Journal, vol. 76 (1987), pp. 150–67Google Scholar; Schulhofer, Stephen, “Harm and Punishment: A Critique of Emphasis on the Results of Conduct in the Criminal Law,” University of Pennsylvania Law Review, vol. 122 (January 1974), pp. 14971607CrossRefGoogle Scholar; Ashworth, Andrew, “Belief, Intent, and Criminal Liability,” eds. Eekelan, J. and Bell, J., Oxford Essays in Jurisprudence (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 3rd ed. 1987).Google Scholar

17 See Model Penal Code, § 2.04(3).

18 See Lambert v. California, 355 U.S. 225, 78 S.Ct. 240, 2 L.Ed.2d 228 (1957).

19 See Bayles, M., Principles of Law: A Normative Analysis (Dordrecht, Boston, Lancaster and Tokyo: D. Reidel Publishing, 1987), pp. 295300CrossRefGoogle Scholar; Hall, Jerome, General Principles of Criminal Law (Indianapolis: Bobbs-Merrill, 1960) pp. 342–51Google Scholar; LaFave, and Scott, , Criminal Law, p. 248Google Scholar; Perkins, and Boyce, , Criminal Law, p. 905Google Scholar; Hart, Henry M., “The Aims of the Criminal Law,” Law and Contemporary Problems, vol. 23 (Summer 1958), pp. 401, 422–25CrossRefGoogle Scholar; Sayre, Frances B., “Public Welfare Offenses,” Columbia Law Review, vol. 33, no. 1 (January 1933) pp. 52, 82CrossRefGoogle Scholar; Singer, Richard, “The Resurgence of Mens Rea: The Rise and Fall of Strict Criminal Liability,” Boston College Law Review, vol. 30, no. 2 (March 1989), pp. 337, 403–8.Google Scholar

20 See Alexander, Larry, “Retributivism and the Inadvertent Punishment of the Innocent,” Law and Philosophy, vol. 2, no. 2 (August 1983), pp. 233–6.CrossRefGoogle Scholar

21 LaFave, & Scott, , Criminal Law, p. 247.Google Scholar

22 See Note, , “Criminal Liability Without Fault: A Philosophical Perspective,” Columbia Law Review, vol. 75, no. 8 (December 1975), pp. 1517, 1564.Google Scholar

23 ibid., p. 1537.

24 ibid., p. 1537. For a rejoinder to this student note's claims on behalf of strict liability, see Singer, Richard, “The Resurgence of Mens Rea: The Rise and Fall of Strict Criminal Liability,” pp. 403–8.Google Scholar

25 Model Penal Code, § 2.02(4)(d).

26 See Note, , “Element Analysis in Defining Criminal Liability: The Model Penal Code and Beyond,” Stanford Law Review, vol. 35 (April 1983), pp. 681, 696.Google Scholar

27 Bayles, , Principles of Law, pp. 295300Google Scholar; Hart, , Punishment and Responsibility, pp. 132–40Google Scholar; Brady, James, “Punishment for Negligence: A Reply to Professor Hall,” Buffalo Law Review, vol. 22, no. 3 (Spring 1972), pp. 107–22Google Scholar; Fletcher, George, “The Theory of Criminal Negligence: A Comparative Analysis,” University of Pennsylvania Law Review, vol. 119, no. 3 (January 1971), pp. 401–38CrossRefGoogle Scholar; Hall, Jerome, “Negligent Behavior Should Be Excluded from Penal Liability,” Columbia Law Review, vol. 63, no. 4 (April 1963), pp. 632–4CrossRefGoogle Scholar; Wasserstrom, Richard, “H.L.A. Hart and the Doctrine of Mens Rea and Criminal Responsibility,” University of Chicago Law Review, vol. 35 (1967), pp. 92126.CrossRefGoogle Scholar

28 See Hart, , Punishment and Responsibility, pp. 147149Google Scholar; Williams, Glanville, The Mental Element in Crime (Jerusalem: Magnes Press, Hebrew University, 1965), pp. 5460Google Scholar; Fletcher, , “Theory of Criminal Negligence,” p. 417Google Scholar; Hall, , “Negligent Behavior,” pp. 632–36Google Scholar; Turner, J.W.C, “The Mental Element in Crimes at Common Law,” Cambridge Law Journal, vol. 6, no. 1 (1936), pp. 31, 44–48.CrossRefGoogle Scholar

29 See authorities in note 27; LaFave, and Scott, , Criminal Law, p. 234.Google Scholar

30 State v. Baker, 1 Kan. App. 2d 568, 571 P.2d 65 (1977).

31 ibid., pp. 570, 571 P.2d, pp., 67–68.

32 People v. Shaughnessey, 66 Misc.2d 19, 319 N.Y.S.2d 626 (1971).

33 State v. Kremer, 262 Minn. 190, 114 N.W.2d 88 (1962).

34 State v. Weller, 4 Conn. Cir. 267, 230 A.2d 242 (1967).

35 State v. Baker, 1 Kan. App. 2d, p. 573, 571 P.2d, p. 69.

36 Kelman, , “Interpretative Construction in the Substantive Criminal Law,” p. 593.Google Scholar

37 See People v. Shaughnessey.

38 Perkins and Boyce define proximate cause as an actual cause which is not so remote in the causation chain that the court will not recognize it as a legal cause of the event in question. It is a question of “fact and degree.” Perkins, and Boyce, , Criminal Law, pp. 774–77.Google Scholar LaFave and Scott add, “one might logically… be harder on those who intended bad results which differ from what they intended, than on those (morally less at fault) whose conduct amounts only to reckless or negligent creation of risks of bad result.” LaFave, and Scott, , Criminal Law, p. 283.Google Scholar

39 See State v. Kremer.

40 See State v. Weller.

41 2 N.Y.2d 133, 157 N.Y.S.2d 558, 138 N.E. 2d 799 (1956).

42 278 F.2d 169 (3rd Cir. 1960).

43 See also People v. Freeman, 61 Cal. App. 2d 110, 142 P.2d 435 (1943); People v. Hardy, 33 Cal. 2d 52, 198 P.2d 865 (1948); People v. Newton, 8 Cal. App. 3d 359, 87 Cal. Rptr. 394 (1970); Hill v. Baxter, 1 Q.B. 277 (1958).

44 31 Ala. App. 334, 17 So. 2d 427 (1944).

45 72 Misc.2d 646, 340 N.Y.S. 2d 77 (1973).

46 For earlier hints in the literature that strict liability and the voluntary act principle are strange bedfellows, see Budd, M. and Lynch, A., “Voluntariness, Causation, and Strict Liability,” Criminal Law Review (January 1978), pp. 74, 75, footnote 6.Google Scholar See also Husak, , Philosophy of Criminal Law, p. 140Google Scholar (obliquely making this point). And see Killbride v. Lake, 1972 N.Z.L.R. 590.

47 Murphy, Jeffrie, “Involuntary Acts and Criminal Liability,” Ethia, vol. 81 (1971), pp. 332, 340–42.CrossRefGoogle Scholar

48 See discussion in text accompanying note 16 supra.

49 4 Wash. App. 908, 484 P.2d 1167 (1971).

50 ibid., p. 917–19, 484 P.2d, p. 1174.

51 ibid., p. 910–11, 484, P.2d, p. 1170.

52 ibid., p. 919, 484 P. 2d, p. 1174.

53 Consider the following defense of combining objective and subjective factors in determining negligence: “A second source of resistance to admitting negligence as a basis of criminal liability is the assumption that legal negligence determinations must remain wholly objective, i.e., exclusively determined by reference to what a reasonable or prudent person would have thought or done in the circumstances. Such fully objective tests have the weakness that they will not be sensitive to those respects in which an individual accused may be disadvantaged, through no fault of his own, as compared with a person or reasonable prudence. But in the absence of good arguments for retaining these objective tests, it seems reasonable to revise Canadian law so that the test of negligence combines an appeal to publicly accepted objective standards of reasonable care with an individualized test of fault or culpability, permitting evidence of the individual's lack of capacity or opportunity to meet those standards to tell against a verdict of negligence.” Baker, Brenda, “Mens Rea, Negligence, and Criminal Law Reform,” Law and Philosophy, vol. 6, no. 1 (April 1987), pp. 53, 82.CrossRefGoogle Scholar

This attempt to weld objective and individualized tests together demonstrates a basic confusion. There is either the accused as we find him, with whatever kinds of problems of memory, prior education, prior choice, etc., that explained the particular choice on the particular occasion – i.e., that explained the particular case of inadvertent negligence – or there are other people with other character traits that we might want to deem to be ordinary reasonable people, purely fictitious people who would or would not have made the choice that the defendant did. There is no way of combining the real defendant and some objective defendant. The only real question is: what is the explanation of why the person did not advert to the risk in the particular case? The relevance of any other question is hard to discern. For example, the relevance of what somebody else would have chosen had that person adverted to the risk is of dubious relevance to the question of what we should do with an individual who did not advert to the risk.

54 Hart, , Punishment and Responsibility, p. 148Google Scholar; Baker, , “Mens Rea, Negligence, and Criminal Law,” pp. 8385Google Scholar; Fletcher, , “Theory of Criminal Negligence,” p. 417.Google Scholar

55 Bayles, , Principles of Law, p. 299.Google Scholar

56 See ibid.

57 This hypothetical case is courtesy of Michael Moore.

58 See Moore, Michael, “Choice, Character, and Excuse,” Social Philosophy & Policy, vol. 7, no. 2 (Spring 1990).CrossRefGoogle Scholar

59 Although I am assuming throughout this essay that culpability in the criminal law is and should be choice-based, not character-based, and I am thus agreeing with Michael Moore on this point – see ibid. – 1 believe that choice and character are two paradoxically-related sides of the same culpability coin. Choice, apart from what it reveals about character, seems inadequate as a basis for praise or blame. But character that has not been chosen – that is a matter of luck – likewise seems inadequate as a basis for praise or blame. See Nagel, Thomas, “Moral Luck,” in Mortal Questions (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1979), pp. 2438.Google Scholar And punishing someone for possessing a bad character, when, through luck, that person has never been in a circumstance in which his character would cause him to make a culpable choice, is also troubling. See ibid. I believe the inseverability of act and character in judgments of culpability is revealed in many of the examples in Moore's essay, despite Moore's conclusion that those examples favor choice-based judgments over character-based ones. Nevertheless, it seems evident from the standard categories of mens rea – purpose, knowledge, recklessness, and (though not a mental state) negligence – that Anglo-American criminal law rests on a choice-based notion of culpability, whether or not such a notion is independent of or intertwined with a character-based notion.

60 See Singer, Richard, “The Resurgence of Metis Rea: The Rise and Fall of Strict Criminal Liability,” p. 406.Google Scholar

Recklessness in the Model Penal Code is defined as a conscious choice to disregard “a substantial and unjustifiable risk.” Model Penal Code, § 2.02(2)(c). The most plausible interpretation of this provision is that to be reckless, the actor need only be aware of the magnitude of the risk; she need not be aware that it would be legally characterized as “substantial and unjustifiable.” Failure to avoid the known or believed risk must, however, manifest culpability – in the language of the Code, “a gross deviation from the standard of conduct that a law-abiding person would observe.” ibid.

Actually, the Code's definition of recklessness suggests conduct somewhat more culpable than the minimum possible degree of culpability. If an actor knowingly takes any unjustifiable risk, no matter how substantial, the actor may be culpable, depending upon whether the choice bespeaks callousness.

61 Milo, Ronald, Immorality (Princeton: Princeton University Press, 1984), p. 83CrossRefGoogle Scholar; Zimmerman, Michael, “Negligence and Moral Responsibility,” Nous, vol. 20, no. 2 (June 1986), p. 199CrossRefGoogle Scholar; Smith, Holly, “Culpable Ignorance,” The Philosophical Review, vol. 92, no. 4 (October 1983), p. 543.CrossRefGoogle Scholar

62 Holly Smith offers the hypothetical case of the secretary asked by her boss to survey the blood types of the office staff as part of an experiment and who culpably fails to do so. As a result, a worker dies from massive bleeding who would have been saved by a transfusion by the paramedics had they known his blood type in time, which they would have had the secretary conducted the survey. The secretary is culpable. Her culpable choice caused the death in fact. But the culpable choice did not “proximately” cause the death. Smith, Holly “Culpable Ignorance,” pp. 550–51.Google Scholar

Actually, Holly Smith's example is just an illustration of the general problem of having liability turn on causation rather than solely on culpable choice. See authorities cited in note 16 supra. Of course, to the extent that we require that culpable choices be expressed in actions, there is always a “proximate cause” issue in relating the culpable choice to the action that expresses it. In other words, even if all criminal liability were to be based on “attempts” regardless of whether the attempts produced harm, we would still need some notion of proximate cause to distinguish “attempts” from mere intentions. I owe this point to Leo Katz.

63 Cf. United States v. Short, 4 C.M.A. 437, 16 C.M.R. 11 (1954) (an assault with intent to commit rape case where an intoxicated soldier failed to understand a Japanese woman's “no,” although we don't know if he skipped any language classes).

64 Kelman, , “Interpretive Construction in the Substantive Criminal Law,” pp. 606–11.Google Scholar

65 See Model Penal Code, § 2.08(2).

66 See Lewis, “The Punishment That Leaves Something to Chance.”

67 See Kelman, , “Strict Liability: An Unorthodox View,” Encyclopedia of Crime and Justice, ed. Kadish, S. (New York: The Free Press, 1983), vol. 4, p. 1517.Google Scholar

68 I, of course, have completely omitted any discussion of the strict liability presented by the absence of a defense for nonculpable ignorance of the criminal law. See, e.g., Model Penal Code, § 2.04(3).