Hostname: page-component-7c8c6479df-ws8qp Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-03-26T10:41:56.340Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

The Limits of Well-Being

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  13 January 2009

Shelly Kagan
Affiliation:
Philosophy, University of Illinois at Chicago

Extract

What are the limits of well-being? This question nicely captures one of the central debates concerning the nature of the individual human good. For rival theories differ as to what sort of facts directly constitute a person's being well-off. On some views, well-being is limited to the presence of pleasure and the absence of pain. But other views push the boundaries of well-being beyond this, so that it encompasses a variety of mental states, not merely pleasure alone. Some theories then draw the line here, limiting well-being to the presence of the appropriately broadened set of mental states. But still others extend the limits of well-being even further, so that it is constituted in part by facts that are not themselves mental states at all; on such views, well-being is partly constituted by states of affairs that are “external” to the individual's experiences.

In this essay, I want to explore some of this debate by focusing on a particular stretch of the dialectic. That is, I want to think hard about a particular connected series of arguments and counterarguments. These arguments – or, at least, the concerns they seek to express – emerge naturally in the give and take of philosophical discussion. Together they make up a rather simple story, whose plot, in very rough terms, is this: first there is an attempt to push the limits of well-being outward, moving from a narrow to a broader conception; then comes the claim that the resulting notion is too broad, and so we must retreat to a narrower conception after all.

Type
Research Article
Copyright
Copyright © Social Philosophy and Policy Foundation 1992

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

References

1 Hereafter I will focus only on the goods of a given theory of well-being (e.g., pleasure); for simplicity, I will not discuss the bads (e.g., pain).

2 Examples are to be found in Griffin, James, Well-Being (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1986)Google Scholar, chapter 1, and in Parfit, Derek, Reasons and Persons (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1984)Google Scholar, appendix I. Although I will not be concerned with the specifics of either of these discussions, I have obviously learned – and taken – a great deal from both of them.

3 The example is Parfit's, from Reasons and Persons, appendix I.

4 I am here influenced by unpublished work by Leonard Katz. See his forthcoming book, Hedonism: A View of Mind and Value.

5 Are there any such desires? Their logical possibility suffices to make my point, but I am intrigued by the empirical question as well. Perhaps certain meditative experiences are too “empty” to allow for the desire at the same time; other experiences might be too “full” or consuming to allow for the concurrent desire, crowding it out.

6 The suggestion was made by Tim Snow, with whom I have discussed this argument with benefit; he has in mind theories like that put forward by Parfit in Part III of Reasons and Persons.

7 In contrast, it is not nearly as plausible to assert that a person's life is comprised solely of facts about that person's body and mind. This raises the intriguing – and generally over-looked – possibility that it might be one thing for a person to be well-off and quite another for that person's life to go well. Unfortunately, I cannot explore this fascinating question here; in this essay, I am considering only the nature of the individual person's well-being.

8 Compare Korsgaard, Christine, “Two Distinctions in Goodness,” Philosophical Review, vol. 92 (1983), pp. 169–95.CrossRefGoogle Scholar

9 Alvin Goldman has helpfully characterized my argument as being: “Yes, yes, I've heard that example before.”

10 Having a life that goes well may plausibly turn out to be one of these goods (or a function of them) –if the quality of my life is indeed distinct from my level of well-being (see note 7).