Hostname: page-component-8448b6f56d-gtxcr Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-04-19T07:21:22.679Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

De-centring the ‘big picture’: The Origins of Modern Science and the modern origins of science

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  05 January 2009

Perry Williams
Affiliation:
Cambridge Wellcome Unit for the History of Medicine, Free School Lane, Cambridge CB2 3RH.

Extract

Like it or not, a big picture of the history of science is something which we cannot avoid. Big pictures are, of course, thoroughly out of fashion at the moment; those committed to specialist research find them simplistic and insufficiently complex and nuanced, while postmodernists regard them as simply impossible. But however specialist we may be in our research, however scornful of the immaturity of grand narratives, it is not so easy to escape from dependence – acknowledged or not – on a big picture. When we define our research as part of the history of science, we implicitly invoke a big picture of that history to give identity and meaning to our specialism. When we teach the history of science, even if we do not present a big picture explicitly, our students already have a big picture of that history which they bring to our classes and into which they fit whatever we say, no matter how many complications and refinements and contradictions we put before them – unless we offer them an alternative big picture.

Type
Research Article
Copyright
Copyright © British Society for the History of Science 1993

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

References

We are very grateful to Jim Secord for his invitation and encouragement to give an earlier version of this paper to the British Society for the History of Science conference ‘Getting the Big Picture’ in May 1991; to the respondents at that meeting, who inspired us to explain certain points more fully; to Nick Jardine and Harmke Kamminga for their expert and critical advice on several matters; and to John Christie, Ole Grell, Jonathan Hodge, Jim Secord, and an anonymous referee for various helpful suggestions. And finally we are grateful to our students, who have been our original audience and our original critics during the ten years that we have been developing this argument.

1 Butterfield, Herbert, The Origins of Modern Science 1300–1800, 2nd edn, London, 1957.Google Scholar The chief rival as an introductory textbook in English is probably The Scientific Revolution 1500–1800: The Formation of The Modern Scientific Attitude, New York, 1954Google Scholar, by Butterfield's pupil, Hall, A. Rupert, now in its second edition as The Revolution in Science 1500–1750, Harlow, 1983.Google Scholar See also Kuhn, Thomas S., The Copernican Revolution: Planetary Astronomy in the Development of Western Thought, Cambridge, Mass., 1957Google Scholar; Gillespie, C. C., The Edge of Objectivity: An Essay in the History of Scientific Ideas, Princeton, 1960Google Scholar; Dijksterhuis, E. J., The Mechanization of the World Picture, Oxford, 1961Google Scholar; Westfall, Richard S., The Construction of Modern Science: Mechanism and Mechanics, New York, 1971.Google Scholar

2 The title was also used by Koyré for a series of lectures at Johns Hopkins University in 1951. See his From the Closed World to the Infinite Universe, Baltimore, 1957, p. ix.Google Scholar Compare also the sub-title of Hall, , 1954, op. cit. (1)Google Scholar. ‘The origins of modern science’ was also the title of Chapter 1 of Alfred North Whitehead's Science and the Modern World, New York, 1925Google Scholar, the printed version of his Lowell lectures given the same year; he too was referring to the seventeenth century.

3 Others, including other authors in this issue of the BJHS, would probably prefer to express this in the language of postmodernism. We are deliberately not using this language, not on the grounds of disagreement with postmodernism intellectually, but because we believe in using the minimum possible theory in an exposition, and in this case we think that all the necessary ideas can be adequately expressed in plain speech. The moral and political principle behind this stance is analogous to that behind the movement for ‘intermediate technology’, which seeks to develop solutions to the material problems of developing countries using only tools and materials which can be obtained locally – that is to say, without the importing of high technology which would tend to increase economic and political subordination to industrialized countries. The aim is to provide useful assistance in a form which does not lead to exploitative political relationships.

However, for those readers who want to explore how the ideas in this paper relate to postmodernism, we recommend not only the usually-cited Lyotard The Postmodern Condition but also Parusnikova, Zuzana, ‘Is a postmodern philosophy of science possible?’, Studies in History and Philosophy of Science (1992), 23, 2137CrossRefGoogle Scholar, which unusually for a work on postmodernism is not itself written in postmodern language.

4 Porter, Roy, ‘The scientific revolution: a spoke in the wheel?’, in Revolution in History (ed. Porter, Roy and Teich, Mikuláš), Cambridge, 1986, 290316CrossRefGoogle Scholar, see 295. Precedents for the concept can be traced back to the eighteenth century; see Christie, John R. R., ‘The development of the historiography of science’, in Companion to the History of Modern Science (ed. Olby, R. C., Cantor, G. N., Christie, J. R. R. and Hodge, M. J. S.), London, 1990, 522, especially 79Google Scholar; also Cohen, I. Bernard, Revolution in Science, Cambridge, Mass., 1985, 51101.Google Scholar

5 For very clear evidence of this in the American context, see Thackray, Arnold, ‘The pre-history of an academic discipline: the study of the history of science in the United States, 1891–1941’, in Transformation and Tradition in the Sciences: Essays in Honor of I. Bernard Cohen (ed. Mendelsohn, Everett), Cambridge, 1984, 395420, especially 402–5.Google Scholar

6 Meyerson, Emile, Identity and Reality, London, 1930Google Scholar; original French edition, 1908. Popper, K. R., The Logic of Scientific Discovery, London, 1959Google Scholar; original German edition, 1935.

7 Thouless, Robert H., Straight and Crooked Thinking, 1st edn, London, 1930.Google Scholar For example:‘A really educated democracy, distrustful of emotional phraseology and all the rest of the stock-in-trade of the exploiters of crooked thinking, devoid of reverence for ancient institutions and ancient ways of thinking, could take conscious control of our social development and could destroy those plagues of our civilisation – war, poverty, and crime’ (244–5). A later example of the association of science and freedom (here construed as opposition to Soviet totalitarianism) is Science and Freedom, London, 1955, being the proceedings of a conference convened by the Congress for Cultural Freedom and held in Hamburg 23–26 July 1953.

8 See, for example, the vision of the far distant future (‘Everytown 2036’) in the 1936 film Things to Come, loosely based on Wells, H. G.'s The Shape of Things to Come: The Ultimate Revolution, London, 1933Google Scholar; the 1934 film Plenty of Time for Play (excerpted in the Open University television programme The All-electric Home written and presented by Gerrylynn Roberts, from the course A282 ‘Science, technology and everyday life 1870–1950’); the BBC television film Time on our Hands, first transmitted in 1963.

9 Thackray, , op. cit. (5), 411.Google Scholar

10 Sarton, George, The History of Science and the New Humanism, Bloomington, 1962, original edn 1930Google Scholar; Huxley, Julian, ‘Scientific humanism’, in his What Dare I Think? The Challenge of Modern Science to Human Action and Belief, London, 1931, 149–77.Google ScholarSnow, C. P.'s The Two Cultures and the Scientific Revolution (Cambridge, 1959)Google Scholar was also an expression of this view; it is often forgotten that his reason for pointing out the cultural divide between the arts and the sciences was to complain that arts people did not sufficiently understand and respect the sciences. (Snow's ‘scientific revolution’, incidentally, was the change resulting from the application of science to industry, which he dated not earlier than 1920.)

11 Thackray, , op. cit. (5), 401, 408.Google Scholar The identification of science and human thought was also common; for example, ‘it was as though science or human thought had been held up by a barrier until this moment [i.e. until ‘the scientific revolution’]’ (Butterfield, , op. cit. (1), 7, our emphasis).Google Scholar

12 Cambridge, 1954–, i, 11. Jacob Bronowski's The Ascent of Man was commissioned by the BBC as a counterpart to a similarly epic television series on the history of art by Sir Kenneth Clark; Bronowski, J., The Ascent of Man, London, 1973, 13.Google Scholar One may surmise that it was extremely irritating to Bronowski that the title ‘Civilisation’ had already been commandeered by Clark for his subject; but in the event, his own title made an even stronger claim: that the history of science was the history of human evolution (ibid., 19–20).

13 Butterfield, , op. cit. (1), 7, 5.Google Scholar

14 One problem raised by more recent research, which we are not attempting to discuss here, is that the length of ‘the scientific revolution’ has expanded enormously, as everyone has tried to climb on the bandwagon. Now that it has been extended to the end of the eighteenth century in order to include Lavoisier (Butterfield wrote of ‘The postponed scientific revolution in chemistry’; op. cit. (1), ch. 11), and back to the high medieval period to trace the origins of Galilean mechanics (as in the work of Alistair Crombie, following Pierre Duhem), we are faced with a scientific revolution which spanned maybe five centuries. As Roy Porter has nicely put it, compared with Ten Days that Shook the World, this is an extraordinarily leisurely revolution (op. cit. (4), 293).

15 See, for example, Webster, C., ‘William Harvey's conception of the heart as a pump’, Bulletin of the History of Medicine (1965), 39, 508–17Google ScholarPubMed; Cunningham, Andrew, ‘Fabricius and the “Aristotle project” in anatomical teaching and research at Padua’, in The Medical Renaissance of the Sixteenth Century (ed. Wear, A., French, R. K. and Lonie, I. M.), Cambridge, 1985, 195222Google Scholar; Cunningham, Andrew, ‘William Harvey: the discovery of the circulation of the blood’, in Man Masters Nature: 25 Centuries of Science (ed. Porter, Roy), London, 1987, 6576.Google Scholar

16 A key work here was McGuire, J. E. and Rattansi, P. M., ‘Newton and the “pipes of Pan”’, Notes and Records of the Royal Society (1966), 21, 168–43.CrossRefGoogle Scholar See also Dobbs, Betty Jo Teeter, The Foundations of Newton's Alchemy: Or ‘The Hunting of the Greene Lyon’, Cambridge, 1975.Google Scholar For current thinking on this subject, see Schaffer, Simon, ‘Occultism and reason’, in Philosophy, its History and Historiography (ed. Holland, A. J.), Dordrecht, 1985, 117–43CrossRefGoogle Scholar; and Schaffer, Simon, ‘Godly men and mechanical philosophers: souls and spirits in Restoration natural philosophy’, Science in Context (1987), 1, 5585.CrossRefGoogle Scholar

17 The new interest in Merton is indicated by the reprint in 1970 of Science, Technology and Society in Seventeenth Century England, New York, originally published in Osiris in 1938; and by Puritanism and the Rise of Modern Science: The Merton Thesis (ed. Cohen, I. Bernard), New Brunswick, 1990.Google Scholar See also Shapin, Steven, ‘Discipline and bounding: the history and sociology of science as seen through the externalism-internalism debate’, History of Science (1992), 30, 333–69.CrossRefGoogle Scholar A leading example of how the ‘Merton thesis’ could be reapplied is Webster, Charles, The Great Instauration: Science, Medicine, and Reform, 1626–1660, London, 1975.Google Scholar

18 This was what Biot claimed in his entry on Newton in the Biographie universelle, 2nd edn, Paris, 1854, xxx, 366–404, especially 390 and 401.

19 As Lindberg, David C. and Westman, Robert S. put it in the introduction to their edited collection Reappraisals of the Scientific Revolution, Cambridge, 1990Google Scholar, the last twenty years have seen ‘highly focused studies [which] took root and began subtly to undermine the wall on which Humpty Dumpty sat’ (p. xviii).

20 Feyerabend, Paul, Against Method: Outline of an Anarchistic Theory of Knowledge, London, 1975Google Scholar; Kuhn, Thomas S., The Structure of Scientific Revolutions, 2nd edn, Chicago, 1970.Google Scholar For an interesting exegesis of Feyerabend's much-misunderstood philosophy, see Maia Neto, José R., ‘Feyerabend's scepticism’, Studies in History and Philosophy of Science (1991), 22, 543–55.CrossRefGoogle Scholar

21 Fodor, Jerry, ‘Special sciences, or the disunity of science as a working hypothesis’, Synthese (1974), 28, 77115CrossRefGoogle Scholar; Garfinkel, Alan, Forms of Explanation: Rethinking the Questions in Social Theory, New Haven, 1981, ch. 2.Google Scholar We should admit that many scientists, physicists especially, still believe in the possibility and desirability of reduction and unification. For instance Allport, Phil, ‘Still searching for the Holy Grail’, New Scientist, 5 10 1991, 55–6Google Scholar; Allport works in the High Energy Physics Group at the Cavendish Laboratory in Cambridge. In this article, he reasserts his commitment to the philosophy of Karl Popper, by contrast with that of Nancy Cartwright, and quotes with approval Gerald Holton, a Harvard professor of physics and historian of science, speaking in 1981 of theoretical physics being engaged in a quest for a Holy Grail: nothing less than ‘the mastery of the whole world of experience, by subsuming it ultimately under one unified theoretical structure’. Interestingly, in view of the religious analogy which we draw in the final section of the present paper, Allport suggests that this ‘monotheorist’ ambition could never have become established without a long tradition of monotheist belief.

22 For the radical challenge, see for example Ravetz, Jerome R., Scientific Knowledge and its Social Problems, Oxford, 1971Google Scholar; the Radical Science Journal, which started publication in January 1974. For the feminist challenge, see for example Rose, Hilary, ‘Hand, brain, and heart: a feminist epistemology for the natural sciences’, Signs: A Journal of Women in Culture and Society (19831984), 9, 7390CrossRefGoogle Scholar; Harding, Sandra, The Science Question in Feminism, Milton Keynes, 1986.Google Scholar For the environmentalist challenge, see for example The Limits to Growth (ed. Club of Rome), London, 1972Google Scholar; Only One Earth (ed. Ward, Barbara and Dubos, René), London, 1972.Google Scholar

23 Merchant, Carolyn, The Death of Nature: Women, Ecology, and the Scientific Revolution, San Francisco, 1980.Google ScholarEaslea, Brian, Liberation and the Aims of Science: An Essay on the Obstacles to the Building of a Beautiful World, London, 1973Google Scholar; Witch Hunting, Magic and the New Philosophy: An Introduction to Debates of the Scientific Revolution 1450–1750, Brighton, 1980Google Scholar; Science and Sexual Oppression: Patriarchy's Confrontation with Woman and Nature, London, 1981.Google Scholar

24 For example, Shapin, Steven and Schaffer, Simon, Leviathan and the Air-pump: Hobbes, Boyle, and the Experimental Life, Princeton, 1985.Google Scholar Even more recently, there has appeared The Scientific Revolution in National Context (ed. Porter, Roy and Teich, Mikuláš), Cambridge, 1992CrossRefGoogle Scholar, which unfortunately does not explore the question of what the scientific revolution was or whether it existed at all.

25 Op. cit. (19). The deliberate aim of the collection, and the conference which preceded it, was ‘to offer at least a partial remedy’ for the ‘distressing situation’ of the complete absence of ‘a [general] picture fully consistent with recent developments [in scholarship]’ (pp. xix–xx). ‘Does any unity emerge’ from the articles? they ask rhetorically, and conclude that ‘the reader will have to decide’ (p. xx). If two scholars of such calibre, after several years of effort, can find no unity to put forward, then there is little hope of the rest of us faring any better.

26 Jardine, Nicholas, ‘Writing off the scientific revolution’ (a review of Lindberg and Westman's Reappraisals), Journal of the History of Astronomy (1991), 22, 311–18.CrossRefGoogle Scholar

27 This takes its cue from the usage of Hobsbawm, E. J., The Age of Revolution, 1789–1848, London, 1962.Google Scholar

28 For example, Merchant, , op. cit. (23)Google Scholar, and Easlea, , op. cit. (23)Google Scholar, aimed to rewrite the history of the ‘scientific revolution’ as the origin of the present politically-oppressive way of knowing the world. The recent wave of anti-scientistic writings consistently ascribe to the ‘scientific revolution’ the origin of the scientistic outlook which they criticize; see for example Appleyard, Bryan, Understanding the Present: Science and the Soul of Modern Man, London, Picador, 1992Google Scholar, especially ch. 2, ‘The birth of science’. Mary Midgley's sophisticated and accessible Science as Salvation: A Modern Myth and its Meaning, London, 1992Google Scholar, is a partial exception. While she repeats the common view that it was in the seventeenth century that ‘modern science first arose’(p. 1) and that matter began to be regarded as inert and passive, all interesting properties being attributed to God alone, she also relates present-day scientism to the expulsion of God from the investigation of nature in the nineteenth century. ‘It is surely extraordinary that nineteenth- and twentieth-century thinkers have supposed that they could take over this attitude to matter unaltered, while eliminating the omnipotent Creator who gave sense to it, as well as the immortal soul which took its status from him’(p. 76).

29 Young, Robert M., ‘The historiographic and ideological context of the nineteenth-century debate on man's place in nature’, in Changing Perspectives in the History of Science: Essays in Honour of Joseph Needham (ed. Teich, Mikulàš and Young, Robert M.), London, 1973, 344438.Google ScholarShapin, Steven, ‘History of science and its sociological reconstructions’, History of Science (1982), 20, 158211.CrossRefGoogle Scholar

30 Skinner, Q. R. D., ‘Meaning and understanding in the history of ideas’, History and Theory (1969), 8, 353.CrossRefGoogle ScholarDunn, John M., ‘The identity of the history of ideas’, Philosophy (1968), 43, 85104.CrossRefGoogle ScholarWilson, Adrian and Ashplant, T. G., ‘Whig history and present-centred history’Google Scholar, and Ashplant, T. G. and Wilson, Adrian, ‘Present-centred history and the problem of historical knowledge’, The Historical Journal (1988), 31, 116 and 253–73 respectively.CrossRefGoogle Scholar

31 Rudwick, Martin J. S., The Great Devonian Controversy: The Shaping of Scientific Knowledge Among Gentlemanly Specialists, University of Chicago Press, 1985, 14.CrossRefGoogle Scholar

32 Collingwood, R. G., An Autobiography, first published 1939, reprinted 1978, Oxford University Press, ch. 5Google Scholar, ‘Question and answer’. A recent development of this philosophical argument is Jardine, Nicholas, The Scenes of Inquiry: On the Reality of Questions in the Sciences, Oxford, 1991.Google Scholar

33 The term ‘Whig’ history derives from Butterfield, Herbert, The Whig Interpretation of History, London, 1931.Google Scholar Unfortunately many people use the term as an all-purpose smear for historiography of which they disapprove, without having read The Whig Interpretation, and occasionally without even being aware of its existence. On this issue we recommend Wilson, and Ashplant, , op. cit. (30)Google Scholar. (They propose the term ‘present-centred’ as a more precise and more general substitute for ‘Whig’.)

34 Sadly, there have been virtually no critical discussions of the changing meaning of the word ‘science’. It is probably significant that the most accessible account we know of was not the work of a historian of science: Williams, Raymond, Keywords: A Vocabulary of Culture and Society, London, 1976Google Scholar, s.v. ‘science’. There has been one good study of the word ‘scientist’: Sydney Ross, ‘“Scientist”: the story of a word’, Annals of Science (1962), 18, 6586.Google Scholar This, however, is a good deal less threatening to the discipline; the invention of the word ‘scientist’ can be interpreted in terms of ‘professionalization’ – that is, merely a change in the organization of essentially the same activity.

35 One spectacular instance we have come across is of the title of Newton's 1687 work being rendered into English as ‘Mathematical Principles of Natural Science’.

36 See Cunningham, Andrew, ‘How the Principia got its name; or, taking natural philosophy seriously’, History of Science (1991), 29, 377–92.CrossRefGoogle Scholar

37 The difficulty of finding a term which conveys the sense of Christian belief typical of early modern people and which informed the natural philosopher's view of the discipline and its subject matter (nature as created by God), but which does not oppose such a position to notions of objectivity, secularity, and science, is itself indicative of the distance of the identity of natural philosophy from that of science.

38 Collingwood, , op. cit. (32), 64.Google Scholar

39 The argument of this paragraph is put in more detail in Cunningham, Andrew, ‘Getting the game right: some plain words on the identity and invention of science’, Studies in History and Philosophy of Science (1988), 19, 365–89.CrossRefGoogle Scholar

40 Hodge, M. J. S., ‘Lamarck's science of living bodies’, BJHS (1971), 5, 323–52.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMedOutram, Dorinda, Georges Cuvier: Vocation, Science and Authority in Post-Revolutionary France, Manchester, 1984.Google ScholarLenoir, Timothy, The Strategy of Life: Teleology and Mechanics in Nineteenth Century German Biology, Dordrecht, 1982.Google ScholarPorter, Roy, The Making of Geology: Earth Science in Britain 1660–1815, Cambridge, 1977.Google ScholarCannon, Susan Faye, Science in Culture: The Early Victorian Period, New York, 1978Google Scholar, especially the chapter on ‘The invention of physics’. Crosland, Maurice, The Society of Arcueil: A View of French Science at the Time of Napoleon I, London, 1967.CrossRefGoogle ScholarFox, Robert, ‘The rise and fall of Laplacean physics’, Historical Studies in the Physical Sciences (1974), 4, 89136.CrossRefGoogle ScholarThe Invention of Physical Science: Intersections of Mathematics, Theology and Natural Philosophy since the Seventeenth Century (ed. Nye, Mary Jo, Richards, Joan and Stuewer, Roger), Dordrecht, 1992.CrossRefGoogle ScholarLesch, John, Science and Medicine in France: The Emergence of Experimental Physiology, 1790–1855, Cambridge, Mass., 1984.CrossRefGoogle ScholarAlbury, W. R., ‘Experiment and explanation in the physiology of Bichat and Magendie’, Studies in the History of Biology (1977), 1, 47131.Google ScholarPubMed

41 For Britain see Morell, Jack and Thackray, Arnold, Gentleman of Science: Early Years of the British Association for the Advancement of Science, Oxford, 1981.Google ScholarHall, Marie Boas, All Scientists Now: The Royal Society in the Nineteenth Century, Cambridge, 1984.Google Scholar On France see for instance Outram, Dorinda, ‘Politics and vocation: French science 1793–1830’, BJHS (1980), 13, 2743CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed; Fox, Robert, ‘Science, the university, and the state in nineteenth century France’, in Professions and the French State 1700–1900 (ed. Geison, Gerald), Philadelphia, 1984, 66145Google Scholar; Fox, Robert, ‘Scientific enterprise and the patronage of research in France 1800–70’, Minerva (1973), 11, 442–73.CrossRefGoogle Scholar On Germany see Turner, R. Steven, ‘The growth of professorial research in Prussia, 1818 to 1848 – causes and context’, Historical Studies in the Physical Sciences (1971), 3, 137–82CrossRefGoogle Scholar; on Berlin, see Shaffer, Elinor S., ‘Romantic philosophy and the organization of the disciplines: the founding of the Humboldt University of Berlin’, in Romanticism and the Sciences (ed. Cunningham, Andrew and Jardine, Nicholas), Cambridge, 1990, 3854.Google Scholar

42 Sec the articles in The Development of the Laboratory: Essays on the Place of Experiment in Industrial Civilization (ed. James, Frank A. J. L.), Basingstoke, 1989CrossRefGoogle Scholar; in The Investigative Enterprise: Experimental Physiology in Nineteenth-Century Medicine (ed. Coleman, William and Holmes, Frederic L.), Berkeley, Calif., 1988Google Scholar; and in The Laboratory Revolution in Medicine (ed. Cunningham, Andrew and Williams, Perry), Cambridge, 1992.Google Scholar

43 See, for example, Bilton, Tony et al. , Introductory Sociology, London, 1981Google Scholar, which defines secularization as ‘the process through which religious thinking, practice, and institutions lose their social significance’ (p. 531). The crucial word here is ‘social’.

44 Chadwick, Owen, The Secularization of the European Mind in the Nineteenth Century, Cambridge, 1975.Google Scholar

45 On the Laplace story see Hahn, Roger, ‘Laplace and the mechanistic universe’, in God and Nature: Historical Essays on the Encounter Between Christianity and Science (ed. Lindberg, David C. and Numbers, Ronald L.), Berkeley, California, 1986, 256–76.Google Scholar

46 Morrell, J. B., ‘Brewster and the early British Association for the Advancement of Science’, in ‘Martyr of Science’: Sir David Brewster 1781–1868 (ed. Morrison-Low, A. D. and Christie, J. R. R.), Edinburgh, 1984, 25–9Google Scholar; Morrell, and Thackray, , op. cit. (41), especially 6376, 165–75.Google Scholar For an argument that Whewell's entire philosophy was part of a programme to bring the investigation of the natural world back into the service of the Christian God and the established social order, see Williams, Perry, ‘Passing on the torch: Whewell's philosophy and the principles of English university education’, in William Whewell: A Composite Portrait (ed. Fisch, Menachem and Schaffer, Simon), Oxford, 1991, 117–47.Google Scholar

47 Turner, Frank M., ‘The Victorian conflict between science and religion: a professional dimension’, Isis (1978), 69, 356–76.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMedBrock, W. H. and Macleod, R. M., ‘The scientists' declaration: reflexions on science and belief in the wake of Essays and Reviews 1864–5’, BJHS (1976), 9, 3966.CrossRefGoogle ScholarBarton, Ruth, ‘The X Club: Science, Religion, and Social Change in Victorian England’, Ph.D. thesis, University of Pennsylvania, 1976.Google Scholar

48 On intellectual transformation and liberalism, see Williams, Raymond, Culture and Society, 1780–1950, London, 1958Google Scholar, especially Introduction and chs. 1–2; Abrams, M. H., The Mirror and the Lamp: Romantic Theory and the Critical Tradition, London, 1971Google Scholar; Butler, Marilyn, Romantics, Rebels and Reactionaries: English Literature and its Background 1760–1830, Oxford, 1981Google Scholar; Turner, R. Steven, ‘The growth of professorial research in Prussia, 1818 to 1848–causes and context’, Historical Studies in the Physical Sciences (1971), 3, 137–82CrossRefGoogle Scholar; Heyck, T. W., The Transformation of Intellectual Life in Victorian England, London, 1982Google Scholar; Harvie, Christopher, The Lights of Liberalism: University Liberals and the Challenge of Democracy 1860–86, London, 1976Google Scholar; Collins, Irene, ‘Liberalism and the newspaper press during the French Restoration, 1814–1830’, History (1961), 46, 1732CrossRefGoogle Scholar; Thomas, R. Hinton, Liberalism, Nationalism and the German Intellectuals 1822–1847, Cambridge, 1951.Google Scholar

49 See for example Hobsbawm, Eric and Ranger, Terence (eds.), The Invention of Tradition, Cambridge, 1984.Google Scholar

50 Apparently some people find this claim difficult to countenance; but an argument of this kind was being made as long ago as 1970, by Thomas Kuhn in The Structure of Scientific Revolutions, in the chapter on ‘The invisibility of revolutions’:

Characteristically, textbooks of science contain just a bit of history, either in an introductory chapter or, more often, in scattered references to the great heroes of an earlier age. From such references both students and professionals come to feel like participants in a long-standing historical tradition. Yet the textbook-derived tradition in which scientists come to sense their participation is one that, in fact, never existed. For reasons that are both obvious and highly functional, science textbooks (and too many of the older histories of science) refer only to that part of the work of past scientists that can easily be viewed as contributions to the statement and solution of the texts' paradigm problems [op. cit. (20), 138, our emphasis.]

For some concrete examples of how revolutionary changes have been made invisible by newly-constructed histories, we recommend Functions and Uses of Disciplinary Histories (ed. Graham, Loren, Lepenies, Wolf and Weingart, Peter), Dordrecht, 1983.CrossRefGoogle Scholar

51 On the philosophes see Christie, , op. cit. (4), 78Google Scholar; Cohen, I. Bernard, ‘The eighteenth-century origins of the concept of scientific revolution’, Journal of the History of Ideas (1976), 37, 257–88.CrossRefGoogle Scholar For the classic expression of the Romantic view of the Greeks, and of the supposed ‘rediscovery’ and emulation of the Greek approach in the Renaissance, see Burckhardt, Jacob, History of Greek CultureGoogle Scholar, originally published as Griechische Kultur, 1898–1902; and his Civilization of the Renaissance in Italy, originally published as Kultur der Renaissance, 1860. On the historical roots of this image of the Greeks see Bernal, Martin, Black Athena: The Afroasiatic Roots of Classical Civilisation, Vol. 1, The fabrication of Ancient Greece 1785–1985, London, Free Association Press, 1987Google Scholar; Ferguson, Wallace K., The Renaissance in Historical Thought, Cambridge, Mass., 1948.Google Scholar

52 For an example of‘Whig’ history of science being deployed for political ends, see Tyndall, John, ‘The Belfast address’, in Fragments of Science, 6th edn, 2 vols., London, 1879, ii, 137203.Google Scholar

53 See Butterfield, , op. cit. (33)Google Scholar. See also Bowler, Peter J., The Invention of Progress: The Victorians and the Past, Oxford, 1989.Google Scholar

54 For a perfect example of a Whig politician and historian creating a ‘Whig’ view of the history of the investigation of the natural world, see Lord Macaulay's famous essay on Francis Bacon.

55 As far as Cohen, (op. cit. (4), 97)Google Scholar could find, the term was first used by Kuhn, Thomas S. (‘The function of measurement in modern physical science’, Isis (1961), 52, 161–93, 190)CrossRefGoogle Scholar. However, the term is now also used in other ways; for example, Brush, Stephen G., The History of Modern Science: A Guide to the Second Scientific Revolution, 1800–1950, Ames, Iowa, 1988Google Scholar, uses it to refer to a late-nineteenth, early-twentieth century revolution, associated with the breakdown of classical physics. One author who as long ago as 1974 saw the change around 1800 as having been something like as fundamental as we are proposing was Arnold Thackray. He pointed out that in the 1750s,

not only was the very name and function of the scientist not yet invented, but science in the sense we know and use the term was unfamiliar to the English-speaking world of the mid-eighteenth century. Natural knowledge certainly existed, and… the period's philosophers or men ‘deep in knowledge’ certainly included many … ‘well-versed in natural philosophy’. But the professional norms, occupational structures, values, goals and rewards associated with the scientist were as unknown as the word. [Our emphasis. ‘The industrial revolution and the image of science’ in Science and Values (ed. Thackray, Arnold and Mendelsohn, Everett), New York, 1974, 3.]Google Scholar

56 There is further discussion of the term ‘invention’ in Cunningham, , op. cit. (39).Google Scholar

57 We think it necessary to make this point explicitly, because the report (in the Newsletter of the British Society for the History of Science) of our original conference paper, on which this present paper is based, suggested that we were attempting ‘to seek transcendent criteria of “modernity”’. We were not. As we hope is now clear, we are not attempting to seek transcendent criteria of anything. In fact, that is exactly what we are arguing against.

58 Excerpt from ‘Little Gidding’ in Four Quartets, copyright 1943 by T. S. Eliot and renewed 1971 by Esme Valerie Eliot, reprinted by permission of Harcourt Brace & Company, and Faber and Faber Ltd.

59 Strict neo-Darwinian theory, based on natural selection, implies that evolutionary lines branch like the twigs of a bush: a non-linear and non-hierarchical view of evolution (see, for example, Jay Gould, Stephen, Wonderful Life: The Burgess Shale and the Nature of History, London, 1989, 2745)Google Scholar. Nevertheless, the popular view of evolution is one of a linear, progressive ascent. Peter Bowler has pointed out that it was this view of evolution which prevailed following the publication of the Origin of Species, not the non-teleological view which Darwin's theory of natural selection implied (The Non-Darwinian Revolution: Reinterpreting a Historical Myth, Baltimore and London, 1988).Google Scholar

60 See, for example, Mead, George Herbert, Mind, Self, and Society (ed. Morris, Charles W.), Chicago, 1934Google Scholar; Piaget, Jean, The Child's Conception of Reality (tr. Cook, Margaret), London, 1955.Google Scholar

61 This Christian-centredness is revealed, for example, in the common statement that ‘different religions are worshipping God in different ways’.

62 Smart, Ninian, The Religious Experience of Mankind, New York, 1969, London, 1971Google Scholar; Cupitt, Don, Taking Leave of God, London, 1980Google Scholar; Smith, Wilfred Cantwell, Towards a World Theology: Faith and the Comparative History of Religion, London, 1981Google Scholar; Ward, Keith, A Vision to Pursue: Beyond the Crisis in Christianity, London, 1991Google Scholar; Holm, Jean, The Study of Religions, London, 1977.Google Scholar For both Christian priests and teachers of Religious Education, the practical political problems of living in a liberal multi-cultural (hence multi-faith) society have been an important stimulus to the development of this view. Interesting possibilities for an account of the invention of religion, paralleling our account of the invention of science, are raised by Smith, Wilfred Cantwell, The Meaning and End of Religion, New York, 1962, London, 1978Google Scholar; as John Hick says in his foreword to the 1978 edition, ‘he shows with full historical evidence that the concept of religions, as contraposed ideological communities, is a modern invention which the West, during the last two hundred years or so, has exported to the rest of the world’ (p. xi).

63 The Peters projection is claimed to provide a more accurate representation of the relative size of the Earth's major land areas than the more-familiar Mercator projection, which exaggerates the area of countries further away from the Equator (e.g. Europe). See Peters, Arno, Der Europa-zentrische Charakter unseres geographischen Weltbildes und seine Überwindung, Dortmund, 1976.Google Scholar

64 Much of the literature on the exporting of Western knowledge is based on the assumption that the process has been more-or-less successful; for example, Buck, Peter, American Science and Modern China, 1876–1936, Cambridge, 1980Google Scholar; Bartholomew, James R., The Formation of Science in Japan, New Haven and London, 1989.Google Scholar But interestingly, some recent works have emphasized the difference of the non-Western traditions, hence questioning how completely Western science retained its identity when transplanted. See for example Choudhuri, Arnab Rai, ‘Practising Western science outside the West: personal observations on the Indian scene’, Social Studies of Science (1985), 15, 475505CrossRefGoogle Scholar; Science, Hegemony and Violence: A Requiem for Modernity (ed. Nandy, Ashis), Oxford, 1988Google Scholar; Watanabe, Masao, The Japanese and Western Science (tr. Benfey, Otto Theodor), Philadelphia, 1991, original Japanese edn 1976.Google Scholar

65 This paragraph was inspired by Le Guin, Ursula K., ‘The carrier bag theory of fiction’, in her Dancing at the Edge of the World: Thoughts on Words, Women, Places, London, 1989, 165–70.Google Scholar See also Rothschild, Joan (ed.), Machina ex Dea: Feminist Perspectives on Technology, New York, 1983.Google Scholar An interesting recent attempt at a ‘big picture’ history from an ecological perspective – i.e. of humanity's changing relationship to its environment, through the development of agriculture and industry – is Ponting, Clive, A Green History of the World, London, 1991.Google Scholar

66 This paragraph was inspired by Rose, Hilary, op. cit. (22).Google Scholar