Hostname: page-component-7c8c6479df-p566r Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-03-27T07:16:39.230Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

Friedman's Permanent Income Hypothesis as an Example of Diagnostic Reasoning

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  05 December 2008

Maarten C. W. Janssen
Affiliation:
Erasmus University, Rotterdam
Yao-Hua Tan
Affiliation:
Free University, Rotterdam

Extract

Many recent developments in artificial intelligence (AI) research are relevant for traditional issues in the philosophy of science. One of the developments in AI research we want to focus on in this article is diagnostic reasoning, which we consider to be of interest for the theory of explanation in general and for an understanding of explanatory arguments in economic science in particular. Usually, explanation is primarily discussed in terms of deductive inferences in classical logic. However, in recent AI research it is observed that a diagnostic explanation is actually quite different from deductive reasoning (see, for example, Reiter, 1987). In diagnostic reasoning the emphasis is on restoring consistency rather than on deduction. Intuitively speaking, the problem diagnostic reasoning is concerned with is the following. Consider a description of a system in which the normal behavior of the system is characterized and an observation that conflicts with this normal behavior. The diagnostic problem is to determine which of the components of the system can, when assumed to be functioning abnormally, account for the conflicting observation. A diagnosis is a set of allegedly malfunctioning components that can be used to restore the consistency of the system description and the observation. In this article, this kind of reasoning is formalized and we show its importance for the theory of explanation. We will show how the diagnosis nondeductively explains the discrepancy between the observed and the correct system behavior. The article also shows the relevance of the subject for real scientific arguments by showing that examples of diagnostic reasoning can be found in Friedman's Theory of the Consumption Function (1957). Moreover, it places the philosophical implications of diagnostic reasoning in the context of Mill's aprioristic methodology.

Type
Essays
Copyright
Copyright © Cambridge University Press 1992

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

References

REFERENCES

Blaug, M. 1980. The Methodology of Economics. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Buchanan, B. G., and Shortliffe, E. H. (editors). 1984. Rule-Based Expert Systems: The MYCIN Experiments of the Stanford Heuristic Programming Project. Reading MA: Addison-Wesley.Google Scholar
Cartwright, N. 1983. How the Laws of Physics Lie. Oxford: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Cartwright, N. 1989. Nature's Capacities and their Measurement. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Davis, R., and Hamscher, H.. 1988. “Model-based Reasoning: Trouble Shooting.” In Exploring Artificial Intelligence, edited by Shrobe, H. E., pp. 297346. San Mateo, CA: Morgan Kaufman Publishers.Google Scholar
Etherington, D. 1988. Reasoning with Incomplete Information. London: Pitman.Google Scholar
Friedman, M. 1953. “Essay on the Methodology of Positive Economics.” In Essays in Positive Economics, edited by Friedman, M., pp. 343. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.Google Scholar
Friedman, M. 1957. The Theory of the Consumption Function. Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Hamscher, W. (editor). 1990. Working Notes of the First International Workshop on Principles of Diagnosis, 07 23–25. Palo Alto, CA: Stanford University.Google Scholar
Hausman, D. M. 1989. “Economic Methodology in a Nutshell.” Journal of Economic Perspectives 3:115–27.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Hirsch, A., and de Marchi, N.. 1986. “Making a Case when Theory Is Unfalsifiable.” Economics and Philosophy 2:121.Google Scholar
Janssen, M. C. W., and Tan, Y.-H.. 1991. “Why Friedman's Non-monotonic Reasoning Defies Hempel's Covering Law Model.” Synthese 86:255–84.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Klant, J. J. 1984. Rules of the Game. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Kleer, J. de, and Williams, B.. 1987. “Diagnostic Multiple Faults.” Artificial Intelligence 32:97130.Google Scholar
McCarthy, J. 1980. “Circumscription – A Form of Non-Monotonic Reasoning.” Artificial Intelligence 13:2739.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
McCarthy, J. 1986. “Applications of Circumscription to Formalizing Commonsense Knowledge.” AI journal 28:89116.Google Scholar
Mill, J. S. 1836. “On the Definition of Political Economy and the Method of Investigation Proper to It,” reprinted in Collected Works, Essays on Economy and Society, Vol. 4, pp. 312–35. Toronto: University of Toronto Press.Google Scholar
Reiter, R. 1980. “A Logic for Default Reasoning.” Artificial Intelligence 13:81132.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Reiter, R. 1987. “Diagnostic Reasoning from First Principles. Artificial Intelligence 32:5796.Google Scholar