Hostname: page-component-7c8c6479df-27gpq Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-03-27T12:23:27.999Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

Luther's necessitarian argument in De servo arbitrio

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  28 January 2015

ANDERS KRAAL*
Affiliation:
Department of Philosophy, University of Calgary, 2500 University Drive NW, Calgary, AB T2N 1N4, Canada e-mail: akraal@ucalgary.ca

Abstract

In De servo arbitrio (1525) Luther famously argues that the divine attributes of will, power, foreknowledge, and immutability are incompatible with (human) free will, and hence that free will is a ‘name with no reality’. I survey some earlier explications of Luther's argument in the literature, and reject them as exegetically unsound. I then go on to propose a new explication. On the proposed explication, Luther's argument turns out to be theologically cogent, provided that we follow Luther in understanding the relevant divine attributes in accordance with Augustinian theology.

Type
Articles
Copyright
Copyright © Cambridge University Press 2015 

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

References

Aristotle, (1962) Prior Analytics, Tredennick, H. (tr. & ed.) (Cambridge MA: Harvard University Press).Google Scholar
Augustine, (1963) The City of God against the Pagans, II, Green, W. (tr. & ed.) (Cambridge MA: Harvard University Press).Google Scholar
Augustine, (1968a) The City of God against the Pagans, III, Wiesen, D. (tr. & ed.) (Cambridge MA: Harvard University Press).Google Scholar
Augustine, (1968b) De trinitate, Mountain, W. J. (ed.) (Turnhout: Brepols).Google Scholar
Ayres, L. (2000) ‘The fundamental grammar of Augustine's trinitarian theology’, in Dodaro, R. & Lawless, G. (eds) Augustine and his Critics (London and New York: Routledge), 5176.Google Scholar
Bergmann, M., Moor, J., & Nelson, J. (2004) The Logic Book, 4th edn (New York: McGraw-Hill).Google Scholar
Boehner, P. (1950) Medieval Logic (Manchester: Manchester University Press).Google Scholar
Denzinger, H. (ed.) (1965) Enchiridion symbolorum definitionum et declarationum de rebus fidei et morum, 33rd edn (Freiburg im Breisgau: Herder).Google Scholar
Dinneen, F. (ed.) (1990) Peter of Spain: Language in Dispute: An English Translation of Peter of Spain's ‘Tractatus’ called afterwards SUMMULAE LOGICALES, based on the Critical Edition by de Rijk, L. M. (Philadelphia: John Benjamins Publishing Company).Google Scholar
Erasmus, (1969) De libero arbitrio diatribe sive collatio, Lesowsky, W. (ed.) (Darmstadt: Wissenschaftliche Buchgesellschaft).Google Scholar
Frankfurt, H. (1969) ‘Alternate possibilities and moral responsibility’, The Journal of Philosophy, 66, 829839.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Kolb, R. (2005) Bound Choice, Election, and the Wittenberg Theological Method (Grand Rapids MI: Eerdmans).Google Scholar
Kraal, A. (2011) ‘Logic and divine simplicity’, Philosophy Compass, 6, 282294.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Kraal, A. (2013) ‘Free choice, determinism, and the re-evaluation of Luther in twentieth-century Swedish theology’, Studia Theologica, 67, 2842.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Kraal, A. (forthcoming) ‘Valla-style determinism and the intellectual background of Luther's De servo arbitrio’, Harvard Theological Review.Google Scholar
Lohse, B. (1999) Martin Luther's Theology: Its Historical and Systematic Development, Harrisville, R. A. (ed. & tr.) (Edinburgh: T&T Clark).Google Scholar
Luther, M. (1883–2009) D. Martin Luthers Werke: Kritische Gesammtausgabe, 121 vols (Weimar: Böhlau).Google Scholar
Luther, M. (2006) The Bondage of the Will, Packer, J. I. & Johnston, O. R. (trs & eds) (Grand Rapids MI: Revell).Google Scholar
McSorley, H. J. (1967) Luthers Lehre vom unfreien Willen nach seiner Hauptschrift ‘De servo arbitrio’ im Lichte der biblischen und kirchlichen Tradition (Munich: Hueber).Google Scholar
Oberman, H. (1981) Masters of the Reformation: The Emergence of a New Intellectual Climate in Europe, Martin, D. (tr.) (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press).CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Oberman, H. (1986) The Dawn of the Reformation: Essays in Late Medieval and Early Reformation Thought (Edinburgh: T&T Clark).Google Scholar
O'Daly, G. (1999) Augustine's City of God: A Reader's Guide (Oxford: Clarendon Press).CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Portalié, E. (1960) A Guide to the Thought of Saint Augustine (London: Barnes & Oats).Google Scholar
Stayer, J. M. (2000) Martin Luther, German Saviour (Montreal and Kingston: McGill-Queen's University Press).CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Tarski, A. (2002) ‘On the concept of following logically’, History and Philosophy of Logic, 23, 155196.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Trinkaus, C. (ed.) (1999) Collected Works of Erasmus, LXXVI (Toronto: University of Toronto Press).Google Scholar
Urban, L. (1971) ‘Was Luther a thoroughgoing determinist?’, Journal of Theological Studies, 22, 113139.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
White, G. (1994) Luther as Nominalist: A Study of the Logical Methods used in Martin Luther's Disputations in the Light of their Medieval Background (Helsinki: Luther-Agricola-Society).Google Scholar