Hostname: page-component-76fb5796d-x4r87 Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-04-25T20:01:14.128Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

Anselm: Platonism, language and truth in Proslogion

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  03 September 2010

Sigurd Baark*
Affiliation:
Princeton Theological Seminary, Princeton NJ 08540, USAsigurd.baark@ptsem-edu

Abstract

When the Proslogion is read from within the context of Anselm's De Veritate it seems that Anselm's project is firmly based on theological premises. Anselm works with a two-fold conception of truth. Truth is first of all a quality inherent in the statement itself. It is the correctness (rectitudo) of the statement. Second, truth is the correspondence with the extra-linguistic reality. This second level of truth is accidental to the statement. What provides the link between extra-linguistic reality and the statement is the Word of God, which is the level of true reference, where original statements correspond to the original will of God in the creation. When Plato asks what true knowledge is in the Theatetus, the final answer seems to be that what is needed is a statement which carries its own truth as a certainty of Being and Unity within itself. However, no such statement is presented in the dialogue. The name of God in the Proslogion is such a statement which carries its own truth as a certainty of Being and Unity within itself, in that on the first level of truth (rectituto) it is impossible to deny. As the statement concerns the Being of God and cannot be denied it necessarily overflows into the second level of truth which is correspondence with extra-linguistic reality. Therefore, this article argues that Anselm develops a statement which fulfils the criterion of true knowledge presented in the Theatetus. He manages to do this from the position of faith, which includes a strict theological rationality.

Type
Research Article
Copyright
Copyright © Scottish Journal of Theology Ltd 2010

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

References

1 Here I would like to refer to Nielsen's, Bent FlemmingDie Rationalität der Offenbarungsteologi (Aarhus: Aarhus University Press, 1988)Google Scholar. His insightful interpretation of Karl Barth's reading of Anselm's Proslogion has inspired the following article.

2 Barth, Karl, Anselm: Fides quaerens Intellectum (London: SCM Press, 1960), p. 16Google Scholar.

3 Barth, Karl, The Epistle to the Romans (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1968), p. 8Google Scholar.

4 Barth, Karl, Anselm: Fides quaerens Intellectum (London: SCM Press, 1960), p. 16Google Scholar.

5 Davies, Brian, ‘Anselm and the Ontological Argument’, in Davies, Brian and Leftow, Brian (eds), The Cambridge Companion to Anselm (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2004), p. 158CrossRefGoogle Scholar.

6 Gareth Matthews, ‘Anselm Augustine, and Platonism’, ibid., p. 62.

7 Jaspers, Karl, Plato and Augustine (Orlando, FL: Harcourt Brace & Co., 1962), p. 69Google Scholar.

8 Reale, Giovanni, Toward a New Interpretation of Plato (Washington, DC: The Catholic University of America Press, 1997), p. 33Google Scholar.

9 Matthews, Gareth, ‘Anselm, Augustine, and Platonism’, in Davies, Brian and Leftow, Brian (eds), The Cambridge Companion to Anselm (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2004), p. 82Google Scholar.

10 Krämer, Hans Joachim, Plato and the Foundations of Metaphysics (Albany, NY: State University of New York Press, 1990), p. 77Google Scholar.

11 Ibid., p. 98.

12 See Fink, Jakob Leth, Apori og fornuftskritik hos Platon (SLAGMARK–tidsskrift for idéhistorie; Gylling: Narayana Press, 2006)Google Scholar.

13 Hass, Jørgen, ‘Hvad ved vi om viden?’, in Theatetus (Museum Tusculanums Forlag; Copenhagen: Københavns Universitet, 2007), p. 179Google Scholar.

14 See n. 5.

15 King, Peter, ‘Anselm's Philosophy of Language’, in Davies, Brian and Leftow, Brian (eds), The Cambridge Companion to Anselm (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2004), p. 85Google Scholar.

16 Chandler, Daniel, Semiotics: The Basics (Abingdon: Routledge, 2007), p. 34Google Scholar.

17 King, ‘Anselm's Philosophy of Language’, p. 85.

19 Ibid., p. 86.

21 Ibid., p. 87.

22 Ibid., p. 96.

23 One might note that ‘non est possible naturam aeternitatis pluralitatem admittere’ (EDIV, ch. 15), which again points to the absolute principle of Unity and its connection with intelligibility, which is constantly at work within the Platonic tradition. As Anselm notes: ‘Aeternitates autem plures intelligi nequeunt’ (EDIV, ch. 15).

24 Hopkins, Jasper and Richardson, Herbert, Truth, Freedom, and Evil: Three Philosophical Dialogues (New York: Harper Torchbooks, 1967), p. 14Google Scholar.

25 King, ‘Anselm's Philosophy of Language’, p. 101.

26 Ibid., p. 102.

27 Hopkins and Richardson, Truth, Freedom, and Evil, p. 14.

28 King, ‘Anselm's Philosophy of Language’, p. 103.

29 Russell, Bertrand, ‘General Propositions and Existence’, from The Many-Faced Argument, ed. Hick, John and McGill, Arthur C. (New York: Macmillan Co., 1967), p. 220Google Scholar.

30 Ibid., p. 223.

31 Barth, Anselm: Fides quarens Intellectum, p. 73.

32 Davies, ‘Anselm and the Ontological Argument’, p. 159.

33 Ibid., p. 161.

34 Visser, Sandra and Williams, Thomas, ‘Anselm on Truth’, in Davies, Brian and Leftow, Brian (eds), The Cambridge Companion to Anselm (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2004), p. 219Google Scholar.