Hostname: page-component-8448b6f56d-t5pn6 Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-04-18T17:53:58.568Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

Moderately Massive Modularity

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  08 January 2010

Extract

This paper will sketch a model of the human mind according to which the mind's structure is massively, but by no means wholly, modular. Modularity views in general will be motivated, elucidated, and defended, before the thesis of moderately massive modularity is explained and elaborated.

Type
Papers
Copyright
Copyright © The Royal Institute of Philosophy and the contributors 2003

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

References

Armstrong, D. 1968. A Materialist Theory of the Mind. Routledge.Google Scholar
Atran, S. 2002. ‘Modular and cultural factors in biological understanding’, In Carruthers, P., Stich, S. and Siegal, M. (eds.), The Cognitive Basis of Science. Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Baron-Cohen, S. 1995. Mindblindness. MIT Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Baron-Cohen, S. 1999. ‘Does the study of autism justify minimalist innate modularity?Learning and Individual Differences, 10.Google Scholar
Botterill, G. and Carruthers, P. 1999. The Philosophy of Psychology. Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Buss, D. 1989. ‘Sex differences in human mate preferences: Evolutionary hypotheses tested in 37 cultures’, Behavioral and Brain Sciences, 12.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Carey, S. 1985. Conceptual Change in Childhood. MIT Press.Google Scholar
Carey, S. and Spelke, E. 1994. ‘Domain-specific knowledge and conceptual change’, In Hirshfeld, L. and Gelman, S. (eds.), Mapping the Mind. Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Carruthers, P. 1992. Human Knowledge and Human Nature. Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Carruthers, P. 1996. Language, Thought and Consciousness. Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Carruthers, P. 1998. ‘Thinking in language?: evolution and a modularist possibility’, In Carruthers, and Boucher, J. (eds.), Language and Thought. Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Carruthers, P. 2000. Phenomenal Consciousness: a naturalist theory. Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Carruthers, P. 2002. ‘The roots of scientific reasoning: infancy, modularity, and the art of tracking’, In Carruthers, P., Stich, S. and Siegal, M. (eds.), The Cognitive Basis of Science. Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Carruthers, P. forthcoming a. ‘Is the mind a system of modules shaped by natural selection?’ In Hitchcock, C. (ed.), Great Debates in Philosophy: Philosophy of Science. Oxford: Blackwell.Google Scholar
Carruthers, P. forthcoming b. ‘Distinctively human thinking: modular precursors and components’, In Carruthers, P., Laurence, S. and Stich, S. (eds.), The Structure of the Innate Mind.Google Scholar
Chomsky, N. 1988. Language and Problems of Knowledge. MIT Press.Google Scholar
Cohen, L. 1993. An Essay on belief and Acceptance. Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Cosmides, L. and Tooby, J. 1992. ‘Cognitive adaptations for social exchange’, In Barkow, J., Cosmides, L. and Tooby, J. (eds.), The Adapted Mind. Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Cosmides, L. and Tooby, J. 1994. ‘Origins of domain specificity: the volution of functional organization’, In Dupré, J. 2001. Human Nature and the Limits of Science. Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Evans, J. and Over, D. 1996. Rationality and Reasoning. Psychology Press.Google Scholar
Fiddick, L., Cosmides, L. and Tooby, J. 2000. ‘No interpretation without representation; the role of domain-specific representations and inferences in the Wason selection task’, Cognition, 77.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Fodor, J. 1983. The Modularity of Mind. MIT Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Fodor, J. 1992. ‘A theory of the chil's theory of mind’, Cognition, 44.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Fodor, J. 2000. The Mind doesn't Work that way. MIT Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Frankish, K. 1998a. Natural language and virtual belief. In P., Carruthers and J., Boucher (eds.), Language and Thought. Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Harris, P. 2000. The Work of the Imagination. Blackwell.Google Scholar
Hauser, M. and Carey, S. 1998. ‘Building a cognitive creature from a set of Primitives’, In D., Cummins and C., Allen (eds.), The Evolution of Mind. Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Hermer-Vasquez, L.Spelke, E. and Katsnelson, A. 199). ‘Source of flexibility in human cognition: Dual-task studies of space and language’, Congnitive Psychology, 39.Google Scholar
Job, R. and Surian, L. 1998. ‘A neurocognitive mechanism for folk biology?’, Behavioral and Brain sciences, 21.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Karmiloff-Smith, A. 1992. Beyond Modularity. MIT PressGoogle Scholar
Karmiloff-Smith, A., Klima, E., Bellugi, U.Grant, J., and Baron-Cohn, S. 1995. ‘Is there a social module? Language, face processing and theory of mind in individuals with Williams syndrome’, Journal of Cognitive Neuroscience, 72.Google Scholar
Kitcher, P. 1985. Vaulting Ambition: sociobiology and the quest for human nature. MIT Press.Google Scholar
Laurence, S. and Margolis, E. 2001. ‘The poverty of the stimulus argumentBritish Journal for the Philosophy of Science, 52.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Leslie, A. 1994. ‘ToMM, ToBY and Agency: Core architecture and domain specificity’, In L., Hirschfeld and S., Gelman (eds.), Mapping the Mind. Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Levelt, W. 1989. Speaking. MIT Press.Google Scholar
Lycan, W. 1996. Consciousness and Experience. MIT Press.Google Scholar
Marr, D. 1983 Vision. Freeman.Google Scholar
Mervis, C., Morris, C., Bertrand, J. and Robinson, B. 1999. ‘Williams syndrome: findings from an integrated program of research’, In H., Tager-Flusberg (ed.), Neurodevelopmental Disorder. MIT Press.Google Scholar
Miller, G. 1998. ‘Protean primates: the evolution of adaptive unpredictability in competition and courtship’, In A., Whiten and R., Byrne (eds.), Machiavellian Intelligence II. Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Miller, G. 2000. The Mating Mind. Heinemann.Google Scholar
Nichols, S. and Stich, S. forthcoming. Mindreading. Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
O'Hear, A. 1997. Beyond Evolution. Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Pinker, S. 1997. How the Mind Works. Penguin Press.Google Scholar
Rosenthal, D. 1986. ‘Two concepts of consciousness’, Philosophical Studies, 49.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Rosenthal, D. 1993. ‘Thinking that one thinks’, In M., Davies and G., Humphreys (eds.), Consciousness. Blackwell.Google Scholar
Samuels, R. 1998. ‘Evolutionary psychology and the massive modularity hypothesis’, British Journal for the Philosophy of Science, 49.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Samuels, R. 2000. ‘Massively modular minds: evolutionary psychology and cognitive architecture’, In P., Carruthers and A., Chamberlain (eds.), Evolution and the Human Mind. Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Sartori, G. and Job, R. 1988. ‘The oyster with four legs: a neuro-psychological study on the interaction of semantic and visual information’, Cognitive Neuropsychology, 5.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Smith, N. and Tsimpli, I. 1996. The Mind of a Savant. Blackwell.Google Scholar
Sober, E. and Wilson, D. 1999. Unto Others: the evolution and psychology of unselfish behavior. Harvard University Press.Google Scholar
Spelke, E. 1994. ‘Initial knowledge:six suggestions’, Cognition, 50.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Sperber, D. 1994. ‘The modularity of thought and the epidemiology of representations’, In L., Hirschfeld and S., Gelman (eds.), Mapping the Mind. Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Sperber, D. 1996. Explaining Culture. Blackwell.Google Scholar
Sperber, D. 2002. ‘In defense of massive modularity’, In I., Dupoux (eds.), Language, Brain and Cognition Development. MIT Press.Google Scholar
Tooby, J. and Cosmides, L. 1992. ‘The psychological foundations of culture’, In J., Barkow, L., Cosmides and J., Tooby (eds.), The Adapted Mind. Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Tye, M. 1995. Ten Problems of Consciousness. MIT Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Tye, M. 2000. Consciousness, Color and Content. MIT Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Warrington, E. and Shallice, T. 1984. ‘Category specific impairments’, Brain, 107.CrossRefGoogle Scholar