Hostname: page-component-8448b6f56d-xtgtn Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-04-23T15:47:40.690Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

The Domain of Folk Psychology

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  08 January 2010

Extract

My topic in this paper is social understanding. By this I mean the cognitive skills underlying social behaviour and social coordination. Normal, encultured, non-autistic and non-brain-damaged human beings are capable of an impressive degree of social coordination. We navigate the social world with a level of skill and dexterity fully comparable to that which we manifest in navigating the physical world. In neither sphere, one might think, would it be a trivial matter to identify the various competences which underly this impressive level of performance. Nonetheless, at least as far as interpersonal interactions are concerned, philosophers show a rare degree of unanimity. What grounds our success in these interactions is supposed to be our common mastery of (more or less similar versions of) folk psychology.

Type
Papers
Copyright
Copyright © The Royal Institute of Philosophy and the contributors 2003

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

References

Axelrod, R. 1984. The Evolution of Cooperation (Harmondsworth: Penguin).Google Scholar
Bermúdez, J. L. 2000. ‘A Difference Without A Distinction’, Philosophical Explorations 2, 6382.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Bermúdez, J. L. 2003. Thinking Without Words (New York: Oxford University Press).CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Bermúdez, J. L. and Elton, M. 2000. Personal and Subpersonal: Essays on Psychological Explanation. Special issue of Philosophical Explorations (01 2000).Google Scholar
Carruthers, P. M. and Smith, P. K. 1997. Theories of Theories of Mind (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press).Google Scholar
Currie, G. 1995. ‘Imagination and Simulation’ in Davies, and Stone, (eds) 1995b.Google Scholar
Darwin, C. 1872. The Expression of the Emotions in Man and Animals (London: Murray).CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Davies, M. and Stone, T. 1995a. Folk Psychology (Oxford: Basil Blackwell).Google Scholar
Davies, M. and Stone, T. 1995b. Mental Simulation (Oxford: Basil Blackwell).Google Scholar
Dennett, D. 1969. Content and Consciousness (London: Routledge Kegan Paul).Google Scholar
Dennett, D. 1987. ‘Cognitive Wheels: The Frame Problem of AI’ in Minds, Machines, and Evolution, C., Hookway (ed.) (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press).Google Scholar
Dennett, D. 1996. Kinds of Minds (New York: Basic Books).Google Scholar
von Eckhardt, B. 1994. ‘Folk Psychology and Scientific Psychology’, in S., Guttenplan (ed.) A Companion to the Philosophy of Mind (Oxford: Blackwell).Google Scholar
Fodor, J. A. 1987. Psychosemantics (Cambridge MA: MIT Press).CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Gauthier, D. 1986. Morals by Agreement (Oxford: Oxford University Press).Google Scholar
Gopnik, A. and Meltzoff, A. 1997. Thoughts, Theories and Things (Cambridge MA: MIT Press).Google Scholar
Heal, J. 1996. ‘Simulation, Theory and Content’, in Carruthers, and Smith, 1996.Google Scholar
Lewis, D. 1972. ‘Psychophysical and Theoretical Identifications’, Australasian Journal of Philosophy 50, 249–58.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Minsky, M. 1974/1997. ‘A Framework for Representing Knowledge’ in Mind Design II, J., Haugeland (ed.) (Cambridge MA: MIT Press).Google Scholar
Mithen, 1996. The Prehistory of the Mind (London: Thames and Hudson).Google Scholar
Sellars, R. W. 1956/1997. Empiricism and the Philosophy of Mind (Cambridge MA: MIT Press).Google Scholar
Skyrms, B. 1996. The Evolution of the Social Contract (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press).Google Scholar
Smith, Maynard 1982. Evolution and the Theory of Games (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press).CrossRefGoogle Scholar