Hostname: page-component-8448b6f56d-qsmjn Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-04-16T05:33:02.723Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

The Principle of Conservatism in Cognitive Ethology

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  08 January 2010

Extract

Philosophy of mind is, and for a long while has been, 99% metaphysics and 1% epistemology. Attention is lavished on the question of the nature of mind, but questions concerning how we know about minds are discussed much less thoroughly. University courses in philosophy of mind routinely devote a lot of time to dualism, logical behaviourism, the mind/brain identity theory, and functionalism. But what gets said about the kinds of evidence that help one determine what mental states, if any, an individual occupies? Well, Skinner's puritanical disdain for postulating mental states gets raked over the coals, the problem of other minds gets solved by a perfunctory invocation of the principle of inference to the best explanation, and the Turing test gets discussed, mainly in order to emphasize that it can lead to mistaken answers.

Type
Papers
Copyright
Copyright © The Royal Institute of Philosophy and the contributors 2001

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

References

Allen, C. and Cummins, D. (eds) 1998. The Evolution of Mind (Oxford: Oxford University Press).Google Scholar
Baron-Cohen, S., Tager-Flusberg, H. and Cohen, D. (eds) 1993. Understanding Other Minds: Perspectives from Autism (Oxford: Oxford University Press).Google Scholar
Block, N. 1975: ‘Troubles with Functionalism’, in Savage, W. (ed.) (Minneapolis: University of Minnesota Press), pp. 261325.Google Scholar
Carruthers, P. and Smith, P. (eds) 1995. Theories of Theories of Mind. (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press).Google Scholar
Cheney, D. and Seyfarth, R. 1990. How Monkeys See the World (Chicago: University of Chicago Press).Google Scholar
Dennett, D. 1989. The Intentional Stance (Cambridge, MA: MIT Press).Google Scholar
Heyes, C. 1994. ‘Cues, Convergence, and a Curmudgeon—a Reply to Povinelli’, Animal Behaviour, 48, 242–44.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Heyes, C. M. 1998. ‘Theory of Mind in Nonhuman Primates’, Behavioral and Brain Sciences, 21, 101–48.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Lewin, R. 1980: ‘Evolutionary Theory Under Fire’, Science, 210, 883–87.Google Scholar
Lewis, C. and Mitchell, P. (eds) 1994. Understanding of Mind (Hove, UK: LEA).Google ScholarPubMed
Orzack, S. and Sober, E. (eds) 2001. Adaptationism and Optimality (New York: Cambridge University Press).Google Scholar
Orzack, S. and Sober, E. 2001. ‘Adaptation, Phylogenetic Inertia, and the Method of Controlled Comparisons’, in Orzack, S. and Sober, E. (eds) (New York: Cambridge University Press).Google Scholar
Povinelli, D. 1994. ‘Comparative Studies of Animal Mental State Attribution—a Reply to Heyes’, Animal Behaviour, 48, 239–41.Google Scholar
Povinelli, D., Nelson, K., and Boysen, S. 1990. ‘Inferences about Guessing and Knowing by ChimpanzeesJournal of Comparative Psychology, 104, 203–10.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Premack, D. and Woodruff, G. 1978: ‘Does the Chimpanzee have a Theor of Mind?’, Behavior and Brain Sciences, 4, 515–26.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Reichenbach, H. 1956. The Direction of Time (Berkeley: University of California Press).CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Savage, W. (ed.) 1975. Perception and Cognition—Issues in the Foundations of Psychology. Minnesota Studies in the Philosophy of Science, 9, (Minneapolis: University of Minnesota Press).Google Scholar
Shapiro, L. 1997. ‘The Nature of Nature—Rethinking Naturalistic Theories of Intentionality’, Philosophical Psychology, 10, 309–22.Google Scholar
Sober, E. 1998a. ‘Black Box Inference—When Should an Intervening Variable be Postulated?’, British Journal for the Philosophy of Science, 49, 469–98.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Sober, E. 1998b. ‘Morgan’s Canon.' in Allen, C. and Cummins, D. (eds) The Evolution of Mind (Oxford: Oxford University Press), pp. 224–42.Google Scholar
Sober, E. 1999. ‘Testability’, Proceedings and Addresses of the American Philosophical Association. Also available at www: http://philosophy.wisc.edu/sober.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Sober, E. and Wilson, D. S. 1998. Unto Others—The Evolution and Psychology of Unselfish Behavior (Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press).Google Scholar
Whiten, A. 1993. ‘Evolving a Theory of Mind—the Nature of Non-Verbal Mentalism in Other Primates’, in Baron-Cohen, S., Tager-Flusberg, H., and Cohen, D. (eds) (Oxford: Oxford University Press), pp. 365–96.Google Scholar
Whiten, A. 1994. ‘Grades of Mindreading’, in Lewis, C. and Mitchell, P. (eds.) (Hove, UK: LEA), pp. 4770.Google Scholar
Whiten, A. 1995. ‘When does Smart Behaviour—Reading Become Mind-Reading?’ in Carruthers, P. and P., Smith (eds) (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press), pp. 277–92.Google Scholar
Williams, G. C. 1996. Adaptation and Natural Selection (Princeton: Princeton University Press).Google Scholar
Williams, G. C. 1998. The Fish's Glow (New York: Basic Books).Google Scholar