Hostname: page-component-7c8c6479df-fqc5m Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-03-28T01:01:28.356Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

Genetic Engineering and Environmental Ethics

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  29 July 2009

Andrew Dobson
Affiliation:
Chair of the Politics Department at Keele University, Staffordshire, England.

Extract

When God gave humankind dominion over the earth he may not have known exactly what we would be able to do with it. The technical capacities to which the production and reproduction of our everyday life have given rise have grown at an astonishing and, it seems, ever-increasing rate. The instruments that we use to do work on the world have become sharper and more refined, and the implications of human interventions in the nonhuman environment are much more far-reaching than could have been imagined even forty years ago. It has become something of a cliche to say that our technical abilities have outstripped the wisdom to know when, where, and how we should appropriately use them, but techniques such as genetic engineering invite the dusting-off of the cliche and the asking of the question implicit in it: We know we can splice genes, but should we splice them? We might of course come to the conclusion that we should only splice some of them some of the time, but even arriving at that conclusion presupposes that the ethical question has been asked and answered.

Type
Special Section: Alpha and Omega: Ethics at the Edges of Life
Copyright
Copyright © Cambridge University Press 1997

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

References

Notes

1. There is no need to distinguish between ethical and environmental-ethical for the moment.

2. To the extent that some scientific research is carried out ‘for its own sake’ this is an inaccurate formulation–but it will do for present purposes. In any case, discoveries made after research ‘for its own sake’ will often have practical implications, and so the ethical questions will arise at some point or other.

3. Yanchinski, S. Boom and bust in the bio business. New Scientist 1987; 22 01:46.Google Scholar

4. The Royal Commission on Environmental Pollution. The Release of Genetically Engineered Organ isms into the Environment. London: HMSO 1989.Google Scholar

5. Quoting Stanley Cohen. See note 3. Yanchinski, 1987:26.Google Scholar

6. Holland, A. The biotic community: a philosophical critique of genetic engineering. In: Wheale, P, McNally, R, eds. The Bio-Revolution: Cornucopia or Pandora's Box? London: Pluto Press, 1990.Google Scholar

7. Sagoff, M. Biotechnology and the environment: what is at risk? Agriculture and Human Values 1988.Google Scholar

8. Fox M. Transgenic animals: ethical and animal welfare concerns. See note 6. Wheale, , McNally, , 1990:34.Google Scholar

9. Thompson, S. Biotechnology-Shape of things to come or false promise? Futures 1986;18(4):522.CrossRefGoogle Scholar

10. See, for example, Postgate, J. Fixing the nitrogen fixers. New Scientist 1990;(3 02):57.Google Scholar

11. Chakrabarti, C, Bhargava, P. Chemicals through biotechnology: facts, hopes, dreams and doubts. Impact of Science on Society 1990;157:83.Google Scholar

12. See note 7. Sagoff, 1988:29.Google Scholar

13. Only four of Suzuki, David and Knudtson's, Peter ten 'genethic' principles can be applied outside the human realm; see Genethics: The Ethics of Engineering Life. London: Unwin Hyman, 1990: 334–7.Google Scholar

14. A distinction must be drawn between ‘human-centered’ and ‘human-interested.’ A human-interested ethic is one in which human interests automatically override those of the nonhuman natural world (or certain bits of it). A human-centered ethic is one which recognizes that ethics will derive from human beings because only humans can make moral judgments (so far as we know), but that human interests need not automatically override those of the nonhuman natural world.

15. Green, and Yoxen, use the word biotechnology to describe what I have been referring to as genetic engineering.Google Scholar

16. Green, K, Yoxen, E. The greening of European industry: what role for biotechnology? Futures 1990;22;493.CrossRefGoogle Scholar

17. Stephen, Crespi R. The patenting of genetic resources. Impact of Science on Society 1990;158:175.Google Scholar

18. See note 17. Crespi, Stephen 1990:175.Google Scholar

19. King, D. The patenting of plants and animals: legal, socio-economic and ethical issues. Genetics Forum Briefing Paper, p. 1.Google Scholar

20. See note 19. King nd:2–3.

21. See note 17. Crespi, Stephen 1990:182.Google Scholar

22. See note 19. King nd:13.

23. See note 17. Crespi, Stephen 1990:183.Google Scholar

24. Lindsay, A. Human and animal slavery: a theological critique of genetic engineering.Google Scholar See note 6. Wheale, , McNally, 1990:182.Google Scholar

25. See note 17. Crespi, Stephen 1990:183.Google Scholar

26. See note 19. King nd:14.

27. Bunyard, P, Morgan-Grenville, F. The Green Alternative: Guide to Good Living. London: Methuen, 1987:286.Google Scholar

28. McKibben, B. The End of Nature. Harmondsworth: Penguin, 1990:138.Google Scholar

29. See note 24. Lindsay, 1990.Google Scholar

30. As I pointed out at the beginning of this article.

31. Quoted in Dobson, , ed. The Green Reader. London: Andre Deutsch, 1991; and San Francisco: Mercury House, 1991:239.Google Scholar

32. Holland, A. The biotic community: a philosophical critique of genetic engineering.Google Scholar See note 6. Wheale, , McNally, 1990:167.Google Scholar

33. See note 32. Holland, 1990:167.Google Scholar

34. See note 32. Holland, 1990:167.Google Scholar

35. See note 32. Holland, 1990:168.Google Scholar

36. See, for example, Regan, T., The Case for Animal Rights. Berkeley: The University of California Press, 1983.Google Scholar

37. Rolston, H, III, Environmental ethics: values in and duties to the natural world. In: Herbert, Borman F, Kellert, S, eds. Ecology, Economics, Ethics. New Haven and. London: Yale University Press, 1992:84.Google Scholar

38. Fox, M. Transgenic animals: ethical and animal welfare concerns.Google Scholar See note 6. Wheale, , McNally, 1990:31.Google Scholar

39. This should not, of course, be confused with Marx's technical usage of ‘species-being.’

40. See note 38. Fox, 1990:31.Google Scholar

41. See note 7. Sagoff, 1988:26.Google Scholar

42. See note 38. Fox, 1990:32.Google Scholar

43. In what follows, Rolston, Holmes III uses the word “organism” where Fox talks about “animals” – in this respect, Rolston widens the ethical community further than Fox seems prepared to do.Google Scholar

44. See note 37. Rolston, 1992:77.Google Scholar

45. See note 37. Rolston, 1992:79.Google Scholar

46. See note 37. Rolston, 1992:80.Google Scholar

47. See note 37. Rolston, 1992:80.Google Scholar

48. See note 37. Rolston, 1992:76.Google Scholar

49. See note 32. Holland, 1990:170.Google Scholar

50. See note 32. Holland, 1990:170.Google Scholar

51. See note 37. Rolston, 1992:83.Google Scholar

52. See note 37. Rolston, 1992:85.Google Scholar

53. See note 28. McKibben, 1990:134.Google Scholar

54. See note 28. McKibben, 1990:153.Google Scholar

55. See note 28. McKibben, 1990:194–5.Google Scholar

56. See note 13. Suzuki, , Knudtson, 1990:250.Google Scholar

57. Ryder, R. Pigs will fly.Google Scholar See note 6. McNally, 1990:193.Google Scholar

58. MacKenzie, D. Science milked for all it's worth. New Scientist 1988;(24 03):29.Google Scholar

59. Wilmut, I, Clark, J, Simons, P. A revolution in animal breeding. New Scientist 1988;(7 07):58.Google Scholar

60. Vines, G. New tools to treat genetic diseases. New Scientist 1986;(13 03):41.Google Scholar

61. If some of the surplus meat could find its way to the needy in other parts of the world this argu ment might have less force, but the precedents are not promising and the terms of trade are rarely in favor of the needy.

62. See note 60.Vines, 1986:41.Google Scholar

63. Wilmut, I, Clark, J, Simons, P. A revolution in animal breeding. New Scientist 1988;(07 7):57.Google Scholar

64. See note 63. Wilmut, , Clark, , Simons, 1988:57–8.Google Scholar

65. See note 8. Fox, 1990:31.Google Scholar

66. I have already pointed out that Fox himself develops a more nuanced view than that suggested by this quotation.

67. Although of course these risks need also to be taken into account, and have been the subject of intense debate for as long as genetic engineering has been practised.

68. Holland, A, Chadwick, R. Better by design (unpublished). Advice to the Royal Commission on Environmental Pollution. Holland and Chadwick's remarks are here confined to species, but from an environmental ethical perspective they can be expanded to include ecosystems with little difficulty.Google Scholar

69. Connor, S. Genes on the loose. New Scientist 1988;(26 05):66.Google Scholar