Hostname: page-component-8448b6f56d-jr42d Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-04-23T13:21:34.848Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

Structural power: the limits of neorealist power analysis

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  22 May 2009

Stefano Guzzini
Affiliation:
candidate in Social and Political Science at the European University Institute, Florence, Italy.
Get access

Abstract

Realism explains the ruling of the international system through the underlying distribution of power among states. Increasingly, analysts have found this power analysis inadequate, and they have developed new concepts, most prominently structural power. The usage of structural power actually entails three different meanings, namely indirect institutional power, nonintentional power, and impersonal power. Only the first, however, is compatible with the current neorealist choice-theoretical mode of explanation. This is the basic paradox of recent power approaches: by wanting to retain the central role of power, some international relations and international political economy theory is compelled to expand that concept and to move away from the very theory that claims to be based on power. Neorealism does not take power seriously enough. At the same time, these extensions of the concept are themselves partly fallacious. To account simultaneously for the different meanings of structural power and to avoid a conceptual overload, this article proposes that any power analysis should necessarily include a pair or dyad of concepts of power, linking agent power and impersonal governance. Finally, it sketches some consequences of those concepts for international theory.

Type
Articles
Copyright
Copyright © The IO Foundation 1993

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

References

For helpful comments and suggestions on drafts of this article as early as June 1990, I am indebted to James Coleman, Robert Cox, Stephen Gill, Pierre Hassner, Anna Leander, Steven Lukes, Reinhard Meyers, Heikki Patomäki, Susan Strange, Ole Waever, and the editor and two anonymous referees of International Organization. I would also like to thank Peter Taylor and Holly Wyatt who helped me to improve the language.

1. See, respectively, Sklar, Richard L., “On the Concept of Power in Political Economy,” in Nelson, Dalmas H. and Sklar, Richard L., eds., Towards a Humanistic Science of Politics: Essays in Honor of F. Dunham Wortmuth (Lanham, Md.: University Press of America, 1983), pp. 179206Google Scholar; and Caporaso, James and Haggard, Stephen, “Power in the International Political Economy,” in Stoll, Richard J. and Ward, Michael D., eds., Power in World Politics (Boulder, Colo.: Lynne Rienner Publishers, 1989), pp. 99120Google Scholar. Baldwin's, David A.Interdependence and Power: A Conceptual Analysis,” International Organization 34 (Autumn 1980), pp. 471506CrossRefGoogle Scholar is the last reference in Evans, Graham and Newnham, Jeffrey, eds., The Dictionary of World Politics: A Reference Guide to Concepts, Ideas and Institutions (New York: Harvester Wheatsheaf, 1990), pp. 322–24Google Scholar.

2. Keohane, Robert O. and Nye, Joseph S. Jr, “Power and Interdependence Revisited,” International Organization 41 (Autumn 1987), pp. 725–53CrossRefGoogle Scholar. In particular, see p. 729, wherein Keohane and Nye explicitly subsume liberalism and realism under a rational-actor model but with different conceptions of the nature of environment and other actors' goals. See also Nye, Joseph S. Jr, “Neorealism and Neoliberalism,” World Politics 40 (01 1988), pp. 235–51CrossRefGoogle Scholar; and, explicitly, Keohane, Robert O., “International Institutions: Two Approaches,” in Keohane, Robert, International Institutions and State Power: Essays in International Relations Theory (Boulder, Colo.: Westview Press, 1989), pp. 158–79Google Scholar. For the purpose of this argument, only the neoinstitutionalist and regime approaches that use an economic mode of explanation can be criticized accordingly.

3. See Ashley, Richard, “The Poverty of Neorealism,” in Keohane, Robert O., ed., Neorealism and its Critics (New York: Columbia University Press, 1986), pp. 158203Google Scholar; Wendt, Alexander, “The Agent-Structure Problem in International Relations,” International Organization 41 (Summer 1987), pp. 337–70CrossRefGoogle Scholar; Wendt, Alexander, “Bridging the Theory/Metatheory Gap in International Relations,” Review of International Studies 17 (10 1991), pp. 383–92CrossRefGoogle Scholar; and Hollis, Martin and Smith, Steve, “Beware of the Gurus: Structure and Action in International Relations,” Review of International Studies 17 (10 1991), pp. 399403CrossRefGoogle Scholar. See also the rejoinders: Wendt, Alexander, “Levels of Analysis vs. Agents and Structures: Part III,” Review of International Studies 18 (04 1992), pp. 181–85CrossRefGoogle Scholar; and Hollis, Martin and Smith, Steve, “Structure and Action: Further Comment,” in the same issue, pp. 187–88Google Scholar.

4. This is also a requisite of a strictly positivist approach that insists on the prior clarification of the central variables and their meaning. For a classic statement, see Hempel, Carl G., Aspects of Scientific Explanation and Other Essays in the Philosophy of Science (London: Free Press, 1965)Google Scholar.

5. Connolly, William E., The Terms of Political Discourse, 2d ed. (Oxford: Martin Robertson, 1973)Google Scholar, chap. 1.

6. See especially Lukes, Steven, Power: A Radical View (London: Macmillan, 1974)CrossRefGoogle Scholar.

7. Banks, Michael, “The Inter-paradigm Debate,” in Light, M. and Groom, A. J. R., eds., International Relations: A Handbook of Current Theory (London: Frances Pinter, 1985), pp. 726Google Scholar. For the term “ideology,” in IPE, see Gilpin, Robert, The Political Economy of International Relations (Princeton, N.J.: Princeton University Press, 1987)CrossRefGoogle Scholar. For an impressive list of the widely proposed trilogies, see Volker Rittberger and Hartwig Hummel, “Die Disziplin ‘Internationale Beziehungen’ im deutschsprachigen Raum auf der Suche nach ihrer Identität: Entwicklung und Perspektiven” (The discipline of ‘international relations’ in German-speaking countries in search of its identity: evolution and perspectives”), in Rittberger, Volker, ed., Theorien der intemationalen Beziehungen: Bestandsaufnahme und Forschungsperspektiven (Theories of international relations: the state of the art and research perspectives) (Opladen, Germany: Westdeutscher Verlag, 1990), p. 23CrossRefGoogle Scholar.

8. For this attitude, see especially Holsti, K. J., The Dividing Discipline: Hegemony and Diversity in International Theory (Boston: Allen & Unwin, 1985)Google Scholar.

9. For more details, see Guzzini, Stefano, “T. S. Kuhn and International Relations: International Political Economy and the Inter-paradigm Debate,” Master's thesis, London School of Economics and Political Science, 1987Google Scholar; and Guzzini, Stefano, “The Continuing Story of a Death Foretold: Realism in International Relations/International Political Economy,” EUI Working Papers SPS no. 92/20, (Florence, Italy: European University Institute, 1992)Google Scholar, especially chaps. 10 and 16.

10. For the same metatheoretical division, see Carlsnaes, Walter, “The Agency-Structure Problem in Foreign Policy Analysis,” International Studies Quarterly 36 (09 1992), pp. 245–70CrossRefGoogle Scholar, and in particular p. 249.

11. Wendt, Alexander and Duvall, Raymond, “Institutions and International Order,” in Czempiel, Ernst-Otto and Rosenau, James, eds., Global Changes and Theoretical Challenges (Lexington, Mass.: Lexington Books, 1989), pp. 5173Google Scholar. The quotation is from p. 55.

12. This is now widely acknowledged across rather different conceptualizations. See, for example, Barnes, Barry, The Nature of Power (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1988)Google Scholar; Clegg, Stewart, Frameworks of Power (London: Sage Publications, 1989)CrossRefGoogle Scholar; Merritt, Richard L. and Zinnes, Dina A., “Alternative Indexes of National Power,” in Stoll, Richard J. and Ward, Michael D., eds., Power in World Politics (Boulder, Colo.: Lynne Rienner Publications, 1989), pp. 1128, and in particular p. 27Google Scholar.

13. I use the word “structuralist” in the traditional sense of social theory, where it refers to theories that rely on holistic explanations. Waltz's approach has been, unfortunately for the interdisciplinary debate, sometimes labeled structuralist. I will refer to Waltz as a neorealist.

14. For a similar approach, see Joseph, Sarah, Political Theory and Power (Leiden, The Netherlands: E. J. Brill, 1988)Google Scholar.

15. Banks, Michael, “The Evolution of International Relations,” in Banks, Michael, ed., Conflict in World Society: A New Perspective on International Relations (Brighton, England: Harvester Press, 1984), pp. 321 and 18Google Scholar.

16. For a similar approach, see Kratochwil, Friedrich and Ruggie, John Gerard, “International Organization: A State of the Art on an Art of the State,” International Organization 40 (Autumn 1986), pp. 753–75CrossRefGoogle Scholar.

17. See Haas, Ernst, “The Balance of Power: Prescription, Concept, or Propaganda,” World Politics 5 (07 1953), pp. 442–77CrossRefGoogle Scholar; and Claude, Inis L. Jr, Power and International Relations (New York: Random House, 1962)Google Scholar.

18. James Rosenau distinguishes between “capabilities” as a property concept and “control” as actual influence over outcomes; see his 1976 essay “Capabilities and Control in an Interdependent World,” in his book The Study of Global Interdependence: Essays on the Transnationalization of World Affairs (London: Frances Pinter, 1980), pp. 3552Google Scholar.

19. Keohane, Robert and Nye, Joseph Jr, Power and Interdependence: World Politics in Transition (Boston: Little, Brown, 1977), in particular p. 18Google Scholar. For Baldwin's more systematic account, see the next section of the present article.

20. For examples of the “pluralist” approach, see Dahl, Robert, “Power,” in Sills, David, ed., International Encyclopedia of the Social Sciences, vol. 12, 1968, pp. 405–15Google Scholar; and Polsby, Nelson W., Community Power and Political Theory, rev. ed. (New Haven, Conn.: Yale University Press, 1980)Google Scholar.

21. See, respectively, Bacharach, Peter and Baratz, Morton, Power and Poverty: Theory and Practice (New York: Oxford University Press, 1970)Google Scholar; and Steven Lukes, Power: A Radical View. For the IR analysts, see the following section.

22. Krasner, Stephen D., “Regimes and the Limits of Realism: Regimes as Autonomous Variables,” International Organization 36 (Spring 1982), pp. 497510, and especially p. 499CrossRefGoogle Scholar.

23. For this argument, see Aron, Raymond, Paix et guerre entre les nations (Peace and war between nations), 8th ed. (Paris: Calmann-Lévy, 1984), p. 64Google Scholar.

24. Krasner, Stephen, Structural Conflict (Berkeley: University of California Press, 1985), p. 14Google Scholar. For a very similar approach, see Nye, Joseph S. Jr, “Soft Power,” Foreign Policy 80 (Fall 1990), pp. 153–71, and, in particular, pp. 166–68CrossRefGoogle Scholar. Above the traditional “command power,” he conceives of a form of power, called “co-optive power” or ”soft power,” which (1) expressed in terms of resources, is derived from intangible resources like the rules in regimes and cultural and/or ideological attraction and (2) expressed in terms of power exercises, consists in structuring the situations in which power relations occur.

25. Krasner's argument was made in the context of the U.S. and the U.K. decisions to “react” against this attempt by quitting the United Nations Educational, Scientific, and Cultural Organization (UNESCO).

26. The best general presentation in political theory of the choice-theoretical approach to power remains Brian Barry's 1975 essay, “Power: An Economic Analysis,” reprinted in Brian Barry, Democracy, Power, and Justice (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1989), pp. 222–69. See also Baechler, Jean, Le Pouvoir Pur (Pure power) (Paris: Calmann-Lévy, 1978)Google Scholar; and Bartlett, Randall, Economics and Power: An Inquiry into Human Relations and Markets (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1989)CrossRefGoogle Scholar. Additionally, see Dowding, Keith M., Rational Choice and Political Power (Hants, U. K.: Edward Elgar, 1991)Google Scholar, whose distinction between “outcome power” and “social power” reflects exactly Krasner's twofold approach.

27. On this particular point, see Baldwin, David A., Economic Statecraft (Princeton, N.J.: Princeton University Press, 1985), p. 22Google Scholar; and his 1980 essay “Interdependence and Power: A Conceptual Analysis” reprinted in David A. Baldwin, Paradoxes of Power (New York: Basil Blackwell, 1989), especially p. 207.

28. The term “fungibility” refers to the idea of movable goods that can be freely placed and replaced by others of the same class. It connotes universal applicability or “convertibility” in contrast to context specificity. For Baldwin, money is defined by its fungibility. He obviously refers to an ideal type of money, i.e., the most liquid part of the various money aggregates, and the fact that the standard-of-value function is fulfilled mainly in developed national economies and only to a limited extent on the international level.

29. Keohane follows this approach when, by arguing for issue- or regime-specific analyses, he specifically criticizes Waltz for this fungibility assumption. See Keohane, Robert O., “Theory of World Politics: Structural Realism and Beyond,” in Keohane, , Neorealism and Its Critics, pp.158203, and especially p. 184Google Scholar.

30. Baldwin, , Paradoxes of Power, pp. 25 and 209Google Scholar. For a similar argument, see Wolfers, Arnold, Discord and Collaboration (Baltimore, Md.:The Johns Hopkins University Press, 1962), p. 106Google Scholar. Aron states that only the characteristics of money allow economists to reduce the multiplicity of individual choices to a single scale of preferences. Since neither power nor “national interest” can play this role, economics cannot be the model for international theory. By criticizing Kaplan, Aron thereby anticipates and rejects Waltz's research program. Waltz explicitly acknowledges Aron's argument. He counters by claiming that the missing standard-of-value characteristics of power is not a problem for theory building but a practical problem that arises during its application. He thereby overlooks Aron's argument that the reason why money is not analogous to power lies in the lack of a theoretical analogy between utility and national interest. For the two arguments, see Aron, , Paix et guerre entre les nations, p. 98Google Scholar; and Waltz, Kenneth, “Realist Thought and Neorealist Theory,” Journal of International Affairs 44 (Summer 1990), pp. 2138Google Scholar, respectively.

31. Baldwin, David A., “Power Analysis and World Politics: New Trends Versus Old Tendencies,” in Baldwin, , Paradoxes of Power, p. 134Google Scholar.

32. See ibid.; and Baldwin, , Economic Statecraft, p. 285Google Scholar.

33. Martin, Roderick, The Sociology of Power (London: Routledge and Kegan Paul, 1977), p. 29Google Scholar.

34. Baldwin, David A., “Power and Social Exchange,” in Baldwin, , Paradoxes of Power, p. 125Google Scholar, italics original.

35. The reference definition of hegemonic stability theory has been given by Robert Keohane, “The Theory of Hegemonic Stability and Changes in International Economic Regimes, 1967–1977,” in Holsti, Ole R., Siverson, Randolph M., and George, Alexander L., eds., Change in the International System (Boulder, Colo.: Westview Press, 1980), pp. 131–62Google Scholar. Yet, it seems too much tailored for his regime approach, neglecting the collective-good argument. For a convincing argument, see Snidal, Duncan, “The Limits of Hegemonic Stability Theory,” International Organization 39 (Autumn 1985), pp. 579614, and especially p. 581CrossRefGoogle Scholar.

36. Strange, Susan, “International Political Economy: The Story So Far and the Way Ahead,” in Hollist, W. Ladd and Tullis, F. LaMond, eds., An International Political Economy (Boulder, Colo.: Westview Press, 1985), pp. 1325, and, in particular, p. 15Google Scholar.

37. For a concise presentation of recent power concepts with a similar analysis of Strange's approach, see Badie, Bertrand and Smouts, Marie-Claude, Le retoumement du monde: Sociologie de la scène Internationale (The world's overturning: Sociology of the international scene) (Paris: Presses de la Fondation Nationale des Sciences Politiques & Dalloz, 1992), pp. 148–56Google Scholar.

38. See the following works by Strange, Susan: “What About International Relations?” in Strange, Susan, ed., Paths to International Political Economy (London: George Allen & Unwin, 1984), pp. 183–97, and especially pp. 190–91Google Scholar; and States and Markets: An Introduction to International Political Economy (London: Frances Pinter, 1988)Google Scholar, where this notion is developed most fully. For the empirical analysis of U.S. nondecisions, see Casino Capitalism (London: Basil Blackwell, 1986)Google Scholar, chap. 2.

39. Strange, Susan, “Toward a Theory of Transnational Empire,” in Czempiel, and Rosenau, , Global Changes and Theoretical Challenges, pp. 161–76Google Scholar.

40. With regard to the management of the U.S. dollar, this critique has a longer tradition. For one example, see Aron, Raymond, Les dernières années du siécle (The century's last years) (Paris: Julliard, 1984), p. 44Google Scholar. It is important to note that the power to avoid or to export adjustments can, in the long run, undermine the very base of “national” power. This argument is most thoroughly made in David P. Calleo's work; for example, see The Imperious Economy (Cambridge, Mass.: Harvard University Press, 1982)Google Scholar; and Beyond American Hegemony: The Future of the Western Alliance (New York: Basic Books, 1987)Google Scholar. See also Senghaas, Dieter, Friedensprojekt Europa (Peace project Europe) (Frankfurt/Main: Suhrkamp Verlag, 1992), p. 55Google Scholar.

41. Riker, William H., “Some Ambiguities in the Notion of Power,” in Bell, R., Edwards, D. V., and Wagner, R. H., eds., Political Power A Reader in Theory and Practice (New York: Free Press, 1969), p. 116Google Scholar. The recipelike concept is defined as the production of effects through the manipulation of nature.

42. Baldwin, , Economic Statecraft, p. 26Google Scholar.

43. Riker, , “Some Ambiguities in the Notion of Power,” p. 116Google Scholar.

44. Ibid., p. 117; emphasis added.

45. Morriss, Peter, Power: A Philosophical Analysis (Manchester, U.K.: Manchester University Press, 1987), p. 19Google Scholar; emphasis original. On pages 15–18, Morriss criticizes the pluralists for their excessive empiricism in requiring the actual exercise of power as a condition for its existence. He calls this the “event-fallacy.” For a discussion of both fallacies in IR and IPE, see Garst, Daniel, “Thucydides and Neorealism,” International Studies Quarterly 33 (03 1989), pp. 3–27, and, in particular, pp. 20–22CrossRefGoogle Scholar.

46. Morriss, , Power: A Philosophical Analysis, p. 54Google Scholar.

47. Ibid., p. 54.

48. Coming to the second side of her power approach, the diffusion not of the effects but of the origins of power, Strange does, however, individualize a privileged actor, the “international business civilization.” In other words, nonintentional power is very unevenly distributed throughout the international power structure. See Strange, Susan, “The Name of the Game,” in Ritopoulos, N., ed., Sea-changes: American Foreign Policy in a World Transformed (New York: Council of Foreign Relations Press, 1990), pp. 238–74Google Scholar.

49. Knorr, Klaus, Power and Wealth: The Political Economy of International Power (London: Macmillan, 1973), pp. 7778CrossRefGoogle Scholar.

50. Baldwin, , “Interdependence and Power,” p. 205Google Scholar.

51. Caporaso, James A., “Introduction to the Special Issue on Dependence and Dependency in the Global System,” and “Dependence, Dependency, and Power in the Global System: A Structural and Behavioral Analysis,” International Organization 32 (Winter 1978), pp. 112 and 13–43, respectivelyCrossRefGoogle Scholar. The quotations are from pages 4 and 28 and allude, of course, to Keohane and Nye's Power and Interdependence.

52. Ibid., pp. 2 and 18. This point has been most elegantly made by Sanjaya Lall, “Is ‘Dependence’ a Useful Concept in Analysing Underdevelopment?” World Development 3 (November–December 1975), pp. 799–810.

53. This ambiguity has been largely neglected in the literature. For an exception, see Debnam, Geoffrey, The Analysis of Power: A Realist Analysis (London: Macmillan, 1984), p. 24CrossRefGoogle Scholar.

54. Caporaso, , “Introduction to the Special Issue on Dependence and Dependency in the Global System,” p. 4Google Scholar.

55. Caporaso, , “Dependence, Dependency, and Power in the Global System,” p. 33Google Scholar. In more recent writings, Caporaso retreats slightly from this latter position. He retains the basic division between relational (agent-based) and structural power approaches. Yet, together with Stephen Haggard, he now concludes that these forms of power are not necessarily competing categories they both refer to (different kinds) of resources that affect outcomes understood as bargains (see their “Power in the International Political Economy”). For a critique of this argument, see the third part of this article.

56. See in particular two works by Gill, Stephen and Law, David: The Global Political Economy (New York: Harvester, 1988)Google Scholar; and Global Hegemony and the Structural Power of Capital,” International Studies Quarterly 33 (12 1989), pp. 475–99CrossRefGoogle Scholar.

57. For a similar account, based on Steven Lukes's three dimensions, see Krause, Keith, “Military Statecraft: Power and Influence in Soviet and American Arms Transfer Relationships,” International Studies Quarterly 35 (09 1991), pp. 313–36CrossRefGoogle Scholar.

58. Gill, and Law, , The Global Political Economy, p. 73Google Scholar.

59. For the definition of capital, see Gill, and Law, , “Global Hegemony and the Structural Power of Capital,” pp. 480–81Google Scholar. Note that the terms “power of markets” “structural power” are sometimes used interchangeably; see Gill, and Law, , The Global Political Economy, p. 97Google Scholar.

60. The state-market nexus “politicizes” (in an Eastonian way) international economic relations. The analysis is centered around the two competing authoritative allocation mechanisms (for values or resources) that exist: states and markets. See Czempiel, Ernst-Otto, Internationale Politik: Ein Konfliktmodell (International politics: A conflict model) (Paderborn, Germany: Schoningh, 1981)Google Scholar; and Ernst-Otto Czempiel, “Internationalizing Politics: Some Answers to the Question of Who Does What to Whom,” in Czempiel, and Rosenau, , Global Changes and Theoretical Challenges, pp. 117–34Google Scholar.

61. Gill, and Law, , “Global Hegemony and the Structural Power of Capital,” p. 485Google Scholar.

62. On the first point, see Morgenthau, Hans J., Politics Among Nations (New York: Knopf, 1947), pp. 342ffGoogle Scholar; and on the second, see Kenneth Waltz, “International Structure, National Force, and the Balance of Power,” reprinted in James Rosenau, ed., International Politics and Foreign Policy: A Reader in Research and Theory (New York: Free Press, 1969), pp. 304–14, at p. 309. Note in this context Antonio Gramsci's interest in the Italian Realist tradition (Niccolò Machiavelli, Gaetano Mosca, Vilfredo Pareto) in Gramsci, Antonio, Noterelle sulla politico del Machiavelli: Quaderno 13 (Notes on Machiavelli's politics: Notebook 13) (Turin: Einaudi, 1981)Google Scholar.

63. Cox insists on the rooting of hegemony in social forces, to avoid repeating Machiavelli; see Cox, Robert, “Gramsci, Hegemony, and International Relations: An Essay in Method,” Millennium 12 (Summer 1983), pp. 162–75, and especially p. 164CrossRefGoogle Scholar.

64. Bobbio, Norberto, “La teoria dello statoe del potere” (The theory of the state and of power), in Rossi, Pietro, ed., Max Weber e Vanalisi del mondo (Max Weber and the analysis of the world) (Turin: Einaudi, 1981), pp. 215–46, and, in particular, p. 226Google Scholar.

65. Foucault, Michel, “Corso del 14 gennaio 1976,” in Foucault, Michel, Microfisica del Potere: Interventi Politici (The microphysics of power: Political interventions) (Turin: Einaudi, 1977), p. 188Google Scholar.

66. For the stress on Herrschaft, see Albrecht, Ulrich, Internationale Politik: Einführung in das System internationaler Herrschaft (International politics: Introduction into the system of international rule) (Munich: Oldenbourg Verlag, 1986)Google Scholar. For the Gramscian wording, see Klein, Bradley S., “Hegemony and Strategic Culture: American Power Projection and Alliance Defence Policies,” Review of International Studies 14 (04 1988), pp. 133–48, and, in particular, p. 134CrossRefGoogle Scholar.

67. The most radical power critique at the metatheoretical level is the poststructuralist branch of feminism. See Runyan, Anne Sisson and Peterson, V. Spike, “The Radical Future of Realism: Feminist Subversions of IR Theory,” Alternatives 16 (Winter 1991), pp. 67106, and, in particular, pp. 75–76 and 97–98CrossRefGoogle Scholar.

68. See Little, Richard, “Deconstructing the Balance of Power: Two Traditions of Thought,” Review of International Studies 15 (04 1989), pp. 87100CrossRefGoogle Scholar; and Kratochwil, Friedrich, “Regimes, Interpretation, and the ‘Science’ of Politics,Millennium 17 (Summer 1988), pp. 263–84CrossRefGoogle Scholar, and especially p. 272.

69. Ashley, Richard, “The Geopolitics of Geopolitical Space: Toward a Critical Social Theory of International Politics,” Alternatives 12 (10 1987), pp. 403–34CrossRefGoogle Scholar, and especially p. 418.

70. Kertzer, David I., Ritual, Politics, and Power (New Haven, Conn.: Yale University Press, 1988), pp. 179 and 180Google Scholar.

71. Bourdieu, Pierre, Outline of a Theory of Practice (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1977), pp. 164 and 165CrossRefGoogle Scholar.

72. Ashley, Richard, “Imposing International Purpose: Notes on a Problematic of Governance,” in Czempiel, and Rosenau, , Global Changes and Theoretical Challenges, pp. 251–90, and, in particular, p. 269Google Scholar.

73. See Waltz's, Kenneth works, Theory of International Politics (Reading, Mass.: Addison Wesley, 1979)Google Scholar; and especially “A Response to My Critics,” in Keohane, , Neorealism and Its Critics, pp. 322–45Google Scholar. In the latter work, Waltz does not respond to the move to the metatheoretical level on which Ashley's critique is pitched.

74. Wrong, Dennis H., Power: Its Forms, Bases, and Uses, 2d ed. (Oxford: Basil Blackwell, 1988), pp. 35Google Scholar.

75. Barbalet, J. M., “Power, Structural Resources, and Agency,” Current Perspectives in Social Theory, vol. 8, 1987, pp. 124, and, in particular, p. 6Google Scholar.

76. One of the reasons for the reluctance to incorporate nonintentional power is the relationship between the concepts of power and responsibility in agent-oriented theories. It seems, however, to be going too far to conclude that since it is difficult to assess responsibility in cases where unintended effects have been produced, such effects must necessarily be excluded from power analyses. The extent of responsibility must be judged case by case. For both the intended and unintended consequences of action, the capacity to effect an outcome (i.e., power) is a necessary but not sufficient condition for an actor's responsibility.

77. Polsby, , Community Power and Political Theory, p. 208Google Scholar.

78. Morriss, , Power: A Philosophical Analysis, p. 100Google Scholar. In both quotations the emphasis is original.

79. Barry, Brian, “The Uses of Power,”in Barry, Democracy, Power, and Justice, p. 315Google Scholar.

80. Morriss, , Power: A Philosophical Analysis, pp. 105–6Google Scholar.

81. For the first charge, see Lukes, Steven, Essays in Social Theory (New York: Columbia University Press, 1977), p. 9CrossRefGoogle Scholar; and for the second, see Wrong, , Power: Its Forms, Bases, and Uses, p. 252Google Scholar.

82. Ward, Hugh, “Structural Power-A Contradiction in Terms? Political Studies 35 (12 1987), pp. 593610CrossRefGoogle Scholar.

83. The French language distinguishes between puissance (Latin potentia) and pouvoir (Latin potestas), where the first term refers to a potential or ability and the second, to an act. Moreover, a third term, Pouvoir, is used to denote centralized power or government. Foucault's insistence on the diffusion of power is explicable as a countermove to a traditional conception of sovereign (i.e., centralized) power.

84. See especially Lukes, Steven, “Power and Authority,” in Bottomore, T. and Nisbet, R., eds., A History of Sociological Analysis (London: Heinemann, 1979), pp. 633–76Google Scholar.

85. For a recent and similar definition of power, see Heikki Patomäki, “Concepts of ‘Action,’ ‘Structure,’ and ‘Power’ in ‘Critical Social Realism’: A Positive and Reconstructive Critique,” Journal for the Theory of Social Behaviour, vol. 21, no. 2, 1991, pp. 221–50, at p. 234CrossRefGoogle Scholar.

86. DuBois, Marc, “The Governance of the Third World: A Foucauldian Perspective on Power Relations in Development,” Alternatives 16 (Winter 1991), pp. 130CrossRefGoogle Scholar.

87. This applies for both of Foucault's later periods. For the 1970s, see Foucault, Michel, Surveiller et punir: Naissance de la prison (Discipline and punishment: The birth of the prison) (Paris: Gallimard, 1975), pp. 3134Google Scholar; and for the 1980s, Bernauer, James and Rasmussen, David, eds., The Final Foucault (Cambridge, Mass.: MIT Press, 1988), particularly pp. 1820Google Scholar.

88. For a critique of this unwelcome “interference of conspiracy theory,” see Wasver, Ole, “Tradition and Transgression in International Relations: A Post-Ashleyan Position, Working paper no. 24/1989 (Copenhagen: Center for Conflict and Peace Research, 1989), p. 23Google Scholar.

89. Dowding, , Rational Choice and Political Power, p. 137Google Scholar.

90. Dreyfus, Hubert L. and Rabinow, Paul, Michel Foucault: Beyond Structuralism and Hermeneutics, 2d ed. (Chicago: The University of Chicago Press, 1983), p. 187Google Scholar.

91. Strange, Susan, “The Myth of Lost Hegemony,” International Organization 41 (Autumn 1987), pp. 551–74. The quotation is from p. 565CrossRefGoogle Scholar.

92. In other words, the reduction of regimes to objects clashes with an implicit shift to an intersubjective ontology; see Kratochwil, and Ruggie, , “International Organization,” pp. 764–65Google Scholar.

93. For a criticism of Waltz's neorealism as unable to account for the change from the medieval to the modern system, see the writings of John G. Ruggie: “Continuity and Transformation in the World Polity: Toward a Neorealist Synthesis,” in Keohane, , Neorealism and Its Critics, pp. 131–57Google Scholar; and Territoriality and Beyond: Problematizing Modernity in International Relations,” International Organization 47 (Winter 1993), pp. 139–74CrossRefGoogle Scholar.

94. Wendt, Alexander, “Anarchy is What States Make of It: The Social Construction of Power Politics,” International Organization 46 (Spring 1992), pp. 391425, and, in particular, p. 397CrossRefGoogle Scholar.

95. For a thorough appraisal of the concept of sovereignty, see the writings of R. B. J. Walker; for example, State Sovereignty and the Articulation of Political Space/Time,” Millennium 20 (Autumn 1991), pp. 445–61CrossRefGoogle Scholar.

96. See Buzan, Barry, Jones, Charles, and Little, Richard, The Logic of Anarchy: Neorealism to Structural Realism (New York: Columbia University Press, 1993)Google Scholar.

97. For a convincing account of the dynamics of power positions that accounts for Caporaso's and Krasner's frameworks as different stages of power institutionalizations and struggles, see Gaventa, John, Power and Powerlessness: Quiescence and Rebellion in an Appalachian Valley (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1980), p. 21Google Scholar.